LIBRARY UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, Class i THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON BY JOHN S. HARRISON, Ph.D. ASSISTANT PROFESSOR OF ENGLISH IN KENYON COLLEGE Hew STURGIS & WALTON COMPANY 1910 All rights reserved 0EKERAI Copyright 1910 By STURGIS & WALTON COMPANY Set up and electrotyped. Published April, 1910 WO In flBemorfam WILLIAM OGDEN HARRISON MARCH 12, 1909 208545 PREFACE The aim of this work is to show the essen tially Platonic quality of Emerson's thought. It is often held that his transcendentalism has its source in the philosophy of Germany, and that his mysticism is an inheritance from the sacred books of the East. But a careful study has convinced the author that Greek thought has been the most important factor in Emer son's intellectual development. Beneath the surface of his days and years there ran a spirit of philosophic inquiry which was fed by re peated readings in the old philosophers of Greece. From these sons of light he drank in large draughts of intellectual day. The author has attempted to show this by a com parative study of Emerson and the Platonists. In his studies the author has been helped by the labors of Dr. E. W. Emerson, whose edition of the Complete Works of Emerson has afforded many valuable suggestions re garding Emerson's acquaintance with the old philosophers. James Elliot Cabot's Memoir PREFACE and Charles Eliot Norton's edition of the Correspondence of Emerson and Carlyle have also been helpful. For the use which the author has made of these three works, he takes pleasure in thanking the publishers, Messrs. Houghton, Mifflin and Company, who kindly granted the necessary permission. To the generosity of Mr. Thomas M. Johnson, of Osceola, Missouri, the author is greatly in debted. It was from him that the rare vol umes of the Platonists were obtained. For his kindness in lending these absolutely essen tial books the author expresses warmest thanks. JOHN S. HARRISON. GAMBIER, OHIO, March 24, 1910. CONTENTS CHAPTER I EMERSON'S PLATONISM 3 CHAPTER II NATURE 32 CHAPTER III S°UL 77 THE OVER-SOUL 80 II INTELLECT 125 III THE WORLD-SOUL 139 CHAPTER IV LOVE AND BEAUTY 145 CHAPTER V ART . . , Y 186 CHAPTER VI MYTHOLOGY 221 CHAPTER VII THE ASCENDENCY OF PLATONISM 263 BIBLIOGRAPHY 3I7 INDEX . ,: . w :.. ,.. w , .321 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON CHAPTER I EMERSON'S PLATONISM THE mind of Emerson may best be stud ied from the standpoint of Platonism. If one examines the chief centers of his teach ing to be found in his conception of nature, soul, love and beauty, art, and mythology, he will find that Emerson in his most character istic utterances is indebted to Plato and the Platonists. In those great intellectual teach ers Emerson found a body of thought which he so thoroughly appropriated that to under stand the character of his mind it is necessary to watch it consciously forming itself in keep ing with the main trend of Platonic specula tion. The Platonism, however, which is thus as cendent in Emerson's thought, is not iden tified with the body of philosophical doctrine 3 4 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON which present-day scholarship assigns to Plato and which for English readers is presented in the volumes of Jowett's translation (1871). Those volumes came to Emerson's shelves, but so late in life as to find him with his work already done. It was the fruits of an earlier era of Platonic scholarship that Emerson en joyed. In the complete translation of Plato made by Thomas Taylor (1804) and in his earlier translation, The Cratylus, Phcedo, Parmenides, and Tinuzus of Plato (1793) Emerson found a rendering of Plato and an interpretation of his doctrine that identified Platonism with the final stage of Hellenic speculation now named Neo-Platonism. The center of that new philosophy was Plotinus and the great commentator and expounder of its doctrines was Proclus. Taylor esteemed the thinking of these men, especially of Proc lus, all important in the right interpretation of Plato, and to render Plato in an English dress "unattended with his Greek interpreters in the same garb," Taylor assured his readers in his Dedication, is to act "like one who gives an invaluable casket, but without the only key by which it can be unlocked." Later the Bohn translation of Plato (1848) came into Emerson's hands, but in spite of EMERSON'S PLATONISM $ its aim to present Plato without "the absurd mysticism and fanatical extravagances which the New Platonists introduced in their inter pretations," 1 it was not able to counteract the effects of Emerson's earlier readings in Tay lor's edition; Emerson still remained at heart a sympathizer with the manner of the later school of Platonism. His readings in other translations of Thomas Taylor are proof of the attraction which the writings of the Platonists had for him. The Select Works of Plotinus, On the Theology of Plato by Proclus, The Commen taries on the Timaus of Plato by the same, The Mysteries of the Egyptians, Chaldeans and Assyrians by lamblichus, The Life of Pythagoras by the same, to which is added a Collection of Pythagoric Sentences, the treat ise On the Nature of the Universe by Ocellus Lucanus, were all translations by Thomas Taylor with which Emerson was familiar. All but the last two he had in his own library at Concord. In them he found a mass of comment culled by Taylor from obscure Pla tonists. To the Select Works of Plotinus was appended an extract from the treatise of Synesius On Providence, which Emerson con- 1 II., General Introduction, p. I. 6 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON sidered "one of the majestic remains of lit erature." * Generally throughout these Taylor translations and especially in the writings of Proclus, Emerson found frequent mention of Chaldean, or Zoroastrian, Oracles. Taylor published a collection of them in the Classical Journal for 1817 and 1818. These oracles were esteemed by Proclus as genuine frag ments of wisdom. Emerson, however, made no inquiry into their genuineness; not caring, he said, "whether they are genuine antiques or modern counterfeits, as I am only con cerned with the good sentences, and it is in different how old a truth is." 2 Emerson read Porphyry also along with other books, "to pass away the cold and rainy season" of i84i.3 The work of this author must have been Tay lor's translation of Porphyry's Select Works. The substance of Porphyry's life of Plotinus was available for him in Taylor's introduc tion to the Select Works of Plotinus. With The Divine Pymander of Hermes Mercurius Trismegistus in the translation made of the work by Dr. Everard in 1650, Emerson also 1 Complete Works, VII., 202. 2 J. E. Cabot, A Memoir of Ralph Waldo Emerson, I., 290, 291. ., II, 449- EMERSON'S PLATONISM 7 had an acquaintance. His reading led him into a translation of the Akhlak-I-Jalaly made by W. F. Thomson (1839), which was the medium through which the philosophy of Plato and Aristotle got into Mahometism. With Taylor's translation of Sallust On the Gods and the World Emerson may also have been familiar, for he quotes from it in Xature. He had Taylor's translation of The Pyth- agoric Sentences of Demophilus. He prob ably availed himself of the other translations of Plotinus made by Thomas Taylor — Five Books of Plotinus, On Suicide, and An Essay on the Beautiful — though no reference by name to these works appear in Emerson. Emerson's reading in the Neo-Platonists was then as vital a thing as his reading in Plato; and his indebtedness to these writers must never be forgotten in explaining his concep tion of Platonism. For the man whose life labors made possi ble the enjoyment of these obscure philoso phers Emerson has the highest praise. "There are also prose poets," he \vrites. "Thomas Taylor, the Platonist, for instance, is really a better man of imagination, a better poet, or perhaps I should say a better feeder 8 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON to a poet, than any man between Milton and Wordsworth." 1 During his visits to England Emerson was constantly inquiring of the men he met whether they had read Taylor. And it was incredible, so he told Wordsworth, that no one in all England knew anything of Thomas Taylor, "whilst in every American library his translations are found." 2 Such re marks testify to the importance which Emer son attached to Taylor's work. The effect of these readings in the Neo- Platonists appears in Emerson's adoption of their manner of interpreting Plato. They consider the highest idea in Plato's scheme of metaphysics the idea of the One as it is treated in the Parmenides. They identify this idea with that of the Good which in the Republic Plato explains is the highest reality. Thus Thomas Taylor, reflecting their method of criticism, writes : "Of all the dogmas of Plato, that concerning the first principle of things as far transcends in sublimity the doctrine of other philosophers of a different sect, on this subject, as this supreme cause of all transcends other causes. For, according to Plato, the highest God, whom in the Republic he calls 1 Complete Works, VIII., 50. 2 Ibid., V., 295. EMERSON'S PLATONISM 9 the good, and in the Parmenides the one, is not only above soul and intellect, but is even superior to being itself. Hence, since every thing which can in any respect be known, or of which anything can be asserted, must be connected with the universality of things, but the first cause is above all things, it is very properly said by Plato to be perfectly ineffa ble. The first hypothesis therefore of his Parmenides, in which all things are denied of this immense principle, concludes as follows: 'The one therefore is in no respect. So it seems. Hence it is not in such a manner as to be one, for thus it would be being, and partici pate of essence: but as it appears, the one neither is one, nor is, if it be proper to believe in reasoning of this kind. It appears so. But can anything either belong to, or be affirmed of that which is not? How can it? Neither therefore does any name belong to it, nor dis course, nor any science, nor sense, nor opinion. It does not appear that there can. Hence it can neither be named, nor spoken of, nor con ceived by opinion, nor be known, nor per ceived by any being. So it seems.' " 1 Emerson follows this manner of reviewing 1 The Works of Plato, translated by Thomas Taylor, I., Introduction, p. 5. io THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON Plato's system. In his essay on Plato he thus sets forth Plato's conception of the highest postulate of thought: "Plato apprehended the cardinal facts. He could prostrate him self on the earth and cover his eyes whilst he adored that which cannot be numbered, or gauged, or known, or named; that of which everything can be affirmed and denied; that 'which is entity and nonentity.' He called it super-essential. He even stood ready, as in the Parmenides, to demonstrate that it was so — that this Being exceeded the limits of intel lect. No man ever more fully acknowledged the Ineffable." ' Modern criticism does not accept this view of the Parmenides. Scholars no longer in terpret Plato from the standpoint of the Neo- Platonists. They consider the Parmenides either as a dialectical exercise or as a subtle attempt of Plato to criticise the earlier Eleatic philosophy from the standpoint of Zeno.2 Consequently they do not co-ordinate the con ception of the One given in the Parmenides with the idea of the Good as elaborated in the Republic. Into the soundness or weakness of 1 Complete Works, IV., 61. 2 The Dialogues of Plato, translated by B. Jowett, III., 225, 227. EMERSON'S PLATONISM 11 such interpretation it is not necessary here to enter; it is sufficient to appreciate the differ ence and to point out Emerson's adherence to the older school of criticism. In contrast to this idea of an ineffable unity of things Emerson places the conception of a dialectic, the aim of which is to give scien tific knowledge; and this dialectic he main tains Plato elaborated. Thus his exposition goes on to say: "Having paid his homage, as for the human race, to the Illimitable, he (Plato) then stood erect, and for the human race affirmed, 'And yet things are knowableP — that is, the Asia in his mind was first heart ily honored — the ocean of love and power, before form, before will, before knowledge, the Same, the Good, the One; and now, re freshed and empowered by this worship, the instinct of Europe, namely, culture, returns; and he cries, 'Yet things are knowable!' They are knowable, because being from one, things correspond. There is a scale; and the correspondence of heaven to earth, of matter to mind, of the part to the whole, is our guide. As there is a science of stars, called astron omy; a science of quantities, called mathe matics ; a science of qualities, called chemis try; so there is a science of sciences — I call it 12 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON Dialectic — which is the Intellect discrimi nating the false and the true. It rests on the observation of identity and diversity; for to judge is to unite to an object the notion which belongs to it." 1 This is a doctrine of the Republic and truth fully reflects Plato's work. The Neo-Pla- tonists of course accepted it and worked it into their mystical scheme although they held to the former idea of an ineffable One as the superior conception. That is, in Neo-Pla- tonism one finds a mystical system arising out of an idealistic philosophy. The conception of a science based on the knowledge of ideas gave them idealism and truthfully reflected Plato. The conception of an ineffable unity of things above all knowledge necessitated a mysticism; and this they professed to find in Plato. Such criticism Emerson accepted and hence the strong Neo-Platonic strain in his ap preciation of Platonism. Emerson's Platonism is broad enough, too, to take in not only the Neo-Platonists but also the earlier thinkers of Greece from Thales on who antedate the appearance of Plato. In these thinkers he found a crude symbolical 1 Complete Works, IV., 62. EMERSON'S PLATONISM 13 explanation of the absolute cause of things which Neo-Platonism had taught him to con sider above all knowledge. "The baffled in tellect," he says, "must still kneel before this cause, which refuses to be named — ineffable cause, which every fine genius has essayed to represent by some emphatic symbol, as, Thales by water, Anaximines by air, Anaxagoras by (NOVS) thought, Zoroaster by fire, Jesus and the moderns by love; and the metaphor of each has become a national religion." 1 Plato when viewed in connection with these earlier Greek speculators is considered by Emerson as the perfect expression of that which they but inadequately stated ; he gave a scientific account of what had before been uttered symbolically. "Before Pericles came the Seven Wise Masters," he writes, "and we have the beginnings of geometry, metaphysics and ethics; then the partialists — deducing the origin of things from flux or water, or from air, or from fire, or from mind. All mix with these causes mythologic pictures. At last comes Plato, the distributor, who needs no barbaric paint, or tattoo, or whooping; for he can define. He leaves with Asia the vast 1 Complete Works, III., 72-73. H THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON and superlative; he is the arrival of accuracy and intelligence. 'He shall be as a god to me, who can rightly divide and define.' " l In thus estimating the place of this early speculation in the evolution of Greek thought Emerson was developing to its utmost a prac tice of Plato and the Platonists. In both are found open critiques of the earlier philoso phers. In Plotinus there is frequent refer ence to the ancients and no opportunity is lost by Proclus to identify the teaching of the early schools with Platonism. And in Plato Emerson found a criticism that set the old thought in vivid contrast to Plato's own con ceptions. In the Sophist the main speaker re views the preceding philosophers and declares that "each of them has related a fable to us, as being boys." 2 This is the identical position that Emerson takes regarding the early Hel lenic thinkers. Into the thought of these Greek thinkers before Plato, Emerson was curious to inquire. In Plutarch's Morals he found a rich mine of quotation and comment in which the earlier Greek philosophers figure conspicuously. * Ibid., IV., 47- 2 The Works of Plato, translated by Thomas Taylor, III., 240. or THE ( UNIVERSITY / EMERSON'S PLATONISM 15 "Plutarch occupies a unique place in liter ature," Emerson writes, "as an encyclopaedia of Greek and Roman antiquity. Whatever is eminent in fact or in fiction, in opinion, in character, in institutions, in science — natural, moral or metaphysical — or in memorable sayings, drew his attention and came to his pen with more or less fulness of record. He is, among prose writers, what Chaucer is among English poets, a repertory for those who want the story without searching for it at first hand — a compend of all accepted tra ditions." 1 In the English Cudworth, too, ' Emerson found many fragments of ancient thought. The work of this Cambridge Pla- tonist of the seventeenth century — The True Intellectual System of the Universe — was per haps the first book to draw Emerson's atten tion to Platonism.2 He read it for the "cita tions from Plato and the philosophers," 3 but found the body of the work dull reading, relieved only by the "magazine of quotations, of extraordinary ethical sentences, the shining summits of ancient philosophy." 4 Emerson 1 Complete Works, X., 297. 2 Ibid., IV, 294. 3 Ibid. */&«/., X., 516. 16 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON was also sufficiently interested in the early Greek thinkers to study their systems as they were outlined in De Gerando's Histoire Com- paree des Systemes de Philosophic (1822). These three sources, Plutarch, Cudworth and De Gerando, were in Emerson's library. Plutarch and Cudworth were great favorites with Emerson; and Plutarch was of value to him other than as a preserver of fragments of ancient thought. His interpretation of cer tain phases of Platonism was very acceptable to Emerson. And yet it was the miscella neous character of Plutarch that Emerson as sociated with his work. "I confess that, in reading him, I embrace the particulars, and carry a faint memory of the argument or gen eral design of the chapter; but he is not less welcome, and he leaves the reader with a rel ish and a necessity for completing his studies." 1 Plutarch and Plato are the only two of the ancient philosophers whom Emer son dignified by special treatment. Plato has the first place as philosopher in his Repre sentative Men and for Goodwin's edition of Plutarch's Morals (1871) Emerson wrote an introduction. His own copy of Plutarch was d., X., 303-304. EMERSON'S PLATONISM 17 the fifth London edition translated by several hands and published in 1718. Pythagoreanism is the most conspicuous phase of ancient Greek thought antecedent to Plato which Emerson blends with his con ception of Platonism. According to the Pythagoreans the universe is a harmony of antagonizing opposites, of which they gave a series of ten: limited and unlimited; odd and even ; one and many; right and left; masculine and feminine; rest and motion; straight and crooked; light and darkness; good and evil; square and oblong. The series is an arbitrary mingling of mathematical, physical and eth ical contrasts and is a deduction from their primary theory that number is the principle of things. A trace of this way of looking at the consti tution of the universe is found in Emerson's exposition of Plato's teaching. Plato's rec ognition of the ineffable unity of things, so Emerson holds, is grounded on the cardinal fact that unity, or identity, lies forever at the base of things. Along with it is the second fundamental conception, variety. "If specu lation," he says, "tends thus to a terrific unity, in which all things are absorbed, action tends i8 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON directly backwards to diversity. The first is the course or gravitation of mind; the second is the power of nature. Nature is the mani fold. The unity absorbs, and melts or re duces. Nature opens and creates. These two principles reappear and interpenetrate all things, all thought; the one, the many. One is being; the other, intellect: one is neces sity; the other freedom: one, rest; the other, motion: one, power; the other, distribution: one, strength; the other, pleasure: one, con sciousness; the other, definition: one, genius; the other, talent: one, earnestness; the other, knowledge: one, possession; the other, trade: one, caste; the other, culture: one, king; the other, democracy: and, if we dare carry these generalizations a step higher, and name the last tendency of both, we might say, that the end of the one is escape from organization — pure science; and the end of the other is the highest instrumentality, or use of means, or executive deity." 1 In such a catalogue the arbitrary balancing of opposites is quite in keeping with the Pythagorean series. Emerson found authority for thus devel oping Plato's philosophy in the critical atti tude of the Platonists toward Pythagorean 1 Complete Works, IV., 51-52. EMERSON'S PLATONISM 19 notions. To the Platonists Pythagoras was an important name in the history of Hellenic thought. "The mathematical disciplines," says Taylor in his introductory remarks on Plato, "were invented by the Pythagoreans, in order to a reminiscence of divine concerns, to which through these as images, they en deavor to ascend." 1 Plato, he adds, teaches the same things through science. Such a view reflects the critical manner of Proclus. It is Pythagoric, according to him, to signify divine concerns through images.2 And in his Commentaries on the Timceus of Plato he allegorizes Plato's account of the ancient war between the Atlantics and the Athenians in agreement with the Pythagorean notion of the antagonism of elements constituting the uni verse. Taylor summarizing the account states that such a view is doubtless to be pre ferred, as more consistent with the nature of the dialogue, for it refers the story of the At lantic war "to the opposition perpetually flourishing in the universe between unity and multitude, bound and infinity, sameness and difference, motion and permanency, from 1 The Works of Plato, translated by Thomas Taylor, I., General Introduction, p. 37. 2 Ibid. 20 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON which all things, the first cause being excepted, are composed." 1 Emerson had consulted De Gerando's His- toire Comparee des Systemes de Philosophic for a knowledge of Pythagorean beliefs and he had found there an account of the series of elements comprising the universe. The idea was at once taken up, for it chimed in with a favorite way of looking at things even from boyhood when "he pleased himself as he lay on his bed with the beauty of the Lord's equilibrium in the Universe."2 His reading in Cousin, however, may have had the effect of clinching this idea so that it became a fixed one in his mind as he con tinued his study of the Platonists. Emerson tells us in 1833 that he had been reading Cousin's lectures and he must have known them in a translation, an Introduction to the History of Philosophy, made by H. G. Lin- berg (i832).3 In this work Cousin explains the categories of the reason and shows how all propositions are reduced to one proposition; "that is, to the opposition between unity and plurality, substance and phenomenon, being 1 Ibid., II., 432-433- 2 Complete Works, I., Biographical Sketch, p. 39. s /&«/., V., 21. EMERSON'S PLATONISM 21 and appearance, identity and difference, and the like." l The relation of unity and multi plicity he dwells upon at some length. He explains that these two fundamental ideas are "two ideas contemporaneous in reason; two, which reason cannot be without, and which moreover arrive at the same time." 2 One cannot be conceived — he adds — without the other. It is in the same strain that Emerson speaks. "We unite all things by perceiving the law that pervades them; by perceiving the superficial differences and the profound resemblances. But every mental act — this very perception of identity or oneness, recog nizes the difference of things. Oneness and otherness. It is impossible to speak or think without embracing both." 3 But whether Emerson is indebted to Cousin or not, his fondness for balancing antagoniz ing elements of thought is a characteristic of his interpretation of one phase of Platonism. And in so doing he was but following a habit of the Platonists themselves. As in all his appropriations from the philosophy of Plato, 2 P. 114. 8 Complete Works, IV., 48. 22 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON he develops the idea of the Pythagoreans in characteristic fashion. A thir_d_si_gnjj&cant phase of Emerson's in terpretation of Platonic doctrine is due to his acquaintance with the writings of Coleridge. In Coleridge's Friend Emerson found an ac count of a scientific method of thought which was built partly on the philosophy of Plato and partly on the teaching of Bacon. The aim of Coleridge's work in his own words was "to lay down and illustrate certain fundamen tal distinctions and rules of intellectual action, which, if well grounded and thoroughly taken up and appropriated, will give to every one the power of working out, under any cir cumstances, the conclusions of truth for him self." 1 In pursuing this aim Coleridge had examined many systems of thought and had finally ended in correlating the philosophy of Bacon with that of Plato. "Thus the dif ference, or rather distinction, between Plato and Lord Bacon," Coleridge tells us, "is simply this: that philosophy being neces sarily bipolar, Plato treats principally of the truth, as it manifests itself at the ideal pole, as the science of intellect (de mundo Intel- 1 The Friend. Complete Works of Samuel Taylor Cole ridge, II. Object and Plan of the Work, p. 8. EMERSON'S PLATONISM 23 ligibili) ; while Bacon confines himself, for the most part, to the same truth, as it is mani fested at the other or material pole, as the science of nature (de mundo sensibili). It is as necessary, therefore, that Plato should direct his inquiries chiefly to those objective truths that exist in and for the intellect alone, the images and representatives of which we construct for ourselves by figure, number, and word; as that Lord Bacon should attach his main concern to the truths which have their -signatures in nature, and which (as he him self plainly and often asserts) may indeed be revealed to us through and with, but never by the senses, or the faculty of sense." * Owing to his acceptance of this reconcili ation of Plato and Bacon, Emerson adopted, as a fixed idea in all philosophic inquiry, the correlation of matter and mind. In accord ance with that idea he studied Plato and the Platonists. The reading of Bacon was thus a congenial task to accompany his study of Plato. In Bacon's Advancement of Learning Emerson found a conception of a First Phi losophy that easily blended with Plato's ideal of speculative inquiry. "Bacon, in the struc ture of his mind," Emerson thus declares, rf., II., 445- 24 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON "held of the analogists, of the idealists, or (as we popularly say, naming from the best example) Platonists." * And so it comes about that an inquiry into the working of Emerson's mind must con sider the composite character of the Plato- nism on which that mind was feeding. The mysticism of Plotinus and the Neo-Platonists generally — Plotinus being the heart of the new school and the culmination of all Greek philosophy — the ancient thought of those early Greek philosophers preceding Plato, especially that of Pythagoras — Plato being considered as the logical outcome of their speculations — and finally, the contention of Coleridge that a philosophy of natural law such as Bacon's is the co-ordinate of a purely speculative theory of ideas — these are the three media through which the teachings of Plato were studied by Emerson and it should not appear strange if in him the light from Plato is somewhat refracted. Only by rec ognizing the character of the sources from which Emerson drew his material can we hope to understand the part which Platonism played in satisfying the needs of his mind. A second consideration which must be 1 Complete Works, V., 239. EMERSON'S PLATONISM 25 borne in mind in a right understanding of Emerson's relation to Plato and the Plato- nists is the manner of Emerson's reading. He was not a philosopher building up a sys tem of thought. Hence he did not study the sources of his Platonism as a professed student of that philosophy whose chief aim is the un derstanding of all the minutiae of Platonic doctrine. It is impossible therefore to recon struct from Emerson's writings a system of Platonism; his mind was constitutionally un fitted for the performance of such a task. His independent spirit, too, forbade such a proceeding. He used his books for their service to his own spiritual needs. "Books are the best of things, well used; abused, among the worst. What is the right use? What is the one end which all means go to effect? They are for nothing but to inspire. I had better never see a book than to be warped by its attraction clean out of my own orbit, and made a satellite instead of a sys tem." 1 And thus in the reading of his Pla tonic books he attends only to those portions that appeal to him. "I think the Platonists may be read for sentences," he explains, "though the reader fails to grasp the argu- 1 Complete Works, I., 89-90. 26 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON ment of the paragraph or chapter. He may yet obtain gleams and glimpses of a more ex cellent illumination from their genius, out valuing the most distinct information he owes to other books. For I hold that the grandeur of the impression the stars and heavenly bodies make on us is surely more valuable than our exact perception of a tub or a table on the ground." 1 And yet such reading is not like the reading in the books he describes by the term Vocabularies, such as Burton's Anatomy of Melancholy. In such a book he occasion ally found a fine sentence but "no high method, no inspiring efflux." 2 And so in characterizing his manner of reading in the Platonists it must not be forgotten that he read sympathetically enough to catch the spirit of Platonism, even though he never mastered his sources as a professed student would have done. It was also Emerson's habit to index his books and to mark the places which held his attention. Of course these indices are not ex haustive, for they were intended for his own personal reference. But they are very val uable in indicating the exact passages in his 1 Ibid., VII., 409. 2 Ibid., VIL, 211. EMERSON'S PLATONISM 27 sources in which he found his "lustres." Along with the marginal markings they show how curious his reading was, for they lead one into footnotes, introductions, and ap pendices, from all of which he gathered ma terial for some of his most distinctive work. An examination of the marked passages alone would indicate a lively interest on his part in the matters they discuss, but when they are studied in the light of his critical attitude to ward Platonism they appear as veritable sources of his thought. Emerson is specific, too, in explaining the peculiar influence which the Platonists ex erted upon him. They were an intellectual tonic. At the close of his essay, Intellect, he pays the following tribute to these writers: "I cannot recite, even thus rudely, laws of the intellect, without remembering that lofty and sequestered class who have been its prophets and oracles, the high-priesthood of the pure reason, the Trismegisti, the expounders of the principles of thought from age to age. When at long intervals we turn over these abstruse pages, wonderful seems the calm and grand air of these few, these great spiritual lords who have walked in the world — these of the old re ligion — dwelling in a worship which makes ' or THE UNIVERSITY or ILIR 28 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON the sanctities of Christianity look parvenues and popular; for 'persuasion is in soul, but necessity is in intellect.' This band of gran dees, Hermes, Heraclitus, Empedocles, Plato, Plotinus, Olympiodorus, Proclus, Synesius and the rest, have somewhat so vast in their logic, so primary in their thinking, that it seems antecedent to all the ordinary distinc tions of rhetoric and literature, and to be at once poetry and music and dancing and as tronomy and mathematics. I am present at the sowing of the seed of the world. With a geometry of sunbeams the soul lays the foun dations of nature. The truth and grandeur of their thought is proved by its scope and ap plicability, for it commands the entire schedule and inventory of things for its illus tration." l Emerson also found a stimulant to the imagination in reading these writers. "The imaginative scholar," he writes in his essay, Books, "will find few stimulants to his brain like these writers. He has entered the Elysian Fields; and the grand and pleasing figures of gods and daemons and daemoni- acal men, of the 'azonic' and the 'aquatic gods/ daemons with fulgid eyes, and all the 1 Complete Works, II., 345, 346. EMERSON'S PLATONISM 29 rest of the Platonic rhetoric, exalted a little under the African sun, sail before his eyes. The acolyte has mounted the tripod over the cave at Delphi; his heart dances, his sight is quickened. These guides speak of the gods with such depth and with such pictorial de tails, as if they had been bodily present at the Olympian feasts. The reader of these books makes new acquaintance with his own mind ; new regions of thought are opened." 1 Plato does not seem to have dazzled Emer son in the way in which his brilliant friends, the Neo-Platonists did. "Plato is a gowns man," he writes ; "his garment, though of pur ple, and almost sky-woven, is an academic robe and hinders action with its voluminous folds." 2 Again he says of Plato, "He never writes in ecstasy, or catches us up into poetic raptures." 3 And yet the reading of Plato was at times a most solemn event in Emer son's life. He told one friend that it was a great day in a man's life when he first read the Symposium.4' Again, he explains that "the scholar must look long for the right hour for 1 Ibid., VII., 203. 2 Ibid., IV., 123. 3 Ibid., IV., 61. ., IV., 307. 30 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON Plato's Timaeus. At last the elect morning arrives, the early dawn — a few lights con spicuous in the heaven, as of a world just created and still becoming — and in its wide leisures we dare open that book." * And to Carlyle he writes : "I had it fully in my heart to write at large leisure in noble mornings, opened by prayer, or by readings of Plato or whomsoever else is dearest to the Morning Muse." 2 Plato, then, though not so dazzling a power over his mind and imagination as the Neo-Platonists, was still a great inspiration. The qualifying language which he uses in speaking of him is due to the fact that as con trasted with the Platonists, Plato lacks the ecstasy in which Neo-Platonism as a system of mysticism lives and moves and has its being. More evidence of like nature to that already adduced can be found in Emerson's utter ances but sufficient has been given to justify the belief in the importance of Platonism as a molding power in Emerson's thinking. By approaching his work and his Platonic sources in the spirit in which he himself came to the task one is able to come to a fair notion *Ibid., VII., 169-170. 2 The Correspondence of Thomas Carlyle and Ralph Waldo Emerson, II., 2. EMERSON'S PLATONISM 31 of his indebtedness to Plato and his school. And although one can not reconstruct a co ordinated scheme of Platonism from Emer son's work, one need not accept the view of Cabot, his biographer and friend, who writes: uln general, to look for the source of any way of thinking of his in the Neo-Platonists, or in any of the books he read, seems to me like tracing the origin of Jacob Behmen's illumi nation to the glitter of the pewter tankard which, he says, awakened in him the con sciousness of divine things." 1 The golden way lies somewhere between this negation and the other; only on a careful analysis of his work will the way be revealed. 1 A Memoir of Ralph Waldo Emerson, L, 291. CHAPTER II NATURE THE dualism in which the speculation of the Platonists culminates underlies Em erson's conception of the constitution of things. "What the world ends in, therefore," writes Plotinus, "is matter and reason, but that from which it arose, and by which it is governed, is soul." 1 In similar strain Emerson opens his exposition of the nature of the universe with the statement that "philosophically con sidered, the universe is composed of Nature and the Soul." 2 These two elements — na ture and soul — are the poles of Emerson's thought as a philosopher concerned with the ultimate postulates of thinking. Nature was the first topic that engaged his attention, al though his final word on the subject was not spoken until he had elaborated his conception of soul. In his Platonic sources there was a wealth 1 Five Books of Plotinus, 123. 2 Complete Works, L, 4. 32 NATURE 33 of speculation on nature. Plato himself had left in his Timceus an account of natural phi losophy of which the portion dealing with the conception of matter, or space, became of prime importance to Plotinus in his specula tion on the same subject. In the third selec tion from Plotinus' Enneads contained in Taylor's translation of the Select Works, Emerson found a full outline of the position of Plotinus on this great topic. Proclus, too, had reviewed the subject as it was handled by the chief Greek thinkers and the passage con taining his account Emerson had indexed under "Nature" in his own copy of The Com mentaries of Proclus on the Timceus of Plato.1 Plutarch had embodied a mass of opinion on nature in his Morals.2 Emer son did not esteem the bulk of these opinions very highly; he thought them very crude; many of them puerile. But, he fails not to add, "Usually, when Thales, Anaximenes or Anaximander are quoted, it is really a good judgment." 3 In Ocellus Lucanus, Emerson had a short treatise on the nature of the uni verse. And finally in Cudworth he found a 1 1., 8-10. 2 Morals, III., 104-193. 3 Complete Works, X., 310. 34 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON Digression Concerning the Plastic Life of Nature, or an Artificial, Orderly and Me thodical Nature.1 From this Digression Emerson extracted a quotation from Plotinus which he used as a motto for the first edition of Nature. "Na ture is but an image or imitation of wisdom, the last thing of the soul; Nature being a thing which doth only do, but not know." 2 The original extract from Cudworth which yielded Emerson his sentence reads: "How doth wisdom differ from that which is called nature? Verily in this manner, that wisdom is the first thing, but nature the last and low est; for nature is but an image or imitation of wisdom, the last thing of the soul, which hath the lowest impress of reason shining upon it; as when a thick piece of wax is thoroughly impressed upon by a seal, that impress, which is clean and distinct in the superior super ficies of it, will in the lower side be weak and obscure; and such is the stamp and signa ture of nature, compared with that of wisdom and understanding, nature being a thing which doth only do, but not know." 3 Later 1 The True Intellectual System of the Universe, I., 217- 280. 2 Complete Works, I., 403-404. 3 The True Intellectual System of the Universe, I., 240. NATURE 35 editions of Nature appeared without this motto; but the firstling of Emerson's mind nevertheless testifies to its author's indebted ness to Platonism. In the quotation from Plotinus is found the conception which characterizes one phase of Emerson's treatment of Nature. This phase is given in his theory of symbolism. Briefly put, the theory can be stated in three proposi tions: (i) "Words are signs of natural facts." (2) "Particular natural facts are symbols of particular spiritual facts." (3) "Nature is the symbol of Spirit." 1 Each of these statements summarizes a teaching of Platonism with which Emerson's reading had made him familiar. In his Cratylus Plato sets forth the notion of the philosophical import of words to the effect that they are imitations of real things; or as Socrates says, "names properly imposed are like the things, of which they are the names laid down, and are resemblances of the things." 2 Here is the source of Emerson's teaching of the symbolic nature of words. The symbolism of things is a recognized tenet of the Platonists. Plutarch, especially, 1 Complete Works, I.. 25. 2 Bohn translation, III., 391. 36 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON is given to elucidating the symbolical meaning of myths, and in his essay, Of Isis and Osiris, busies himself in unfolding the philosophical import of the rites of the ancient Egyptians. In doing so he justifies himself by an appeal to the method of the Pythagoreans. "If, therefore," he urges, "the most approved of the philosophers did not think meet to pass over or disesteem any significant symbol of the Divinity which they observed even in things that had neither soul nor body, I be lieve they regarded yet more those properties of government and conduct which they saw in such natures as had sense, and were endued with soul, with passion, and with moral temper. We are not, therefore, to content ourselves with worshipping these things, but we must worship God through them — as being the more clear mirrors of him, and pro duced by Nature — so as ever worthily to conceive of them as instruments or artifices of that God which orders all things." * So, too, do Emerson and the Platonists agree in the most universal form of statement — namely, that nature is the symbol of spirit. In the Timceus of Plato the Creator is repre- 1 Morals, IV., 134. NATURE 37 sented as fabricating the world after an eternal, intelligible pattern of which this world becomes an image. "To discover, then, the Creator and Father of this universe," says the Timceus, "as well as his work, is indeed difficult; and when discovered, it is impossi ble to reveal him to mankind at large. And this, too, we must consider respecting him, according to which of two patterns he mod elled the world; whether with reference to one subsisting ever in a state of sameness and similarly affected, or with reference to one that is only generated. If this world then is beautiful and its artificer good, he evidently looked to an eternal pattern, but if it be with out beauty, and what it is not lawful to men tion, he must have looked to one that is generated. It is evident, however, to every one that he looked to one that was eternal; for the universe is the most beautiful of gen erated things, and its artificer the best of causes. Being thus generated, then, it has been framed according to principles that can be comprehended by reason and reflection, and ever abides in sameness of being." 1 Stated in the language of Emerson this idea 1 Bohn translation, II., 332-333- 38 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON underlies the third proposition of his sym bolical teaching, namely, that nature is a sym bol of spirit. Thus far the universe has been viewed as it is seen manifested in space, or in its material phase; but Plato's speculation attended to it as it appears under the aspect of time. And just as the substance of the world has a spirit ual counterpart, so the world in time is re lated to a spiritual reality, called eternity. Thus Plato speaks of the world: "When the parent Creator perceived that this created image of the eternal gods had life and mo tion, he was delighted with his work, and by this very delight he was led to consider how he might make it still more to resemble its exemplar. Hence, as the intelligible universe was an eternal animal, he tried to make this [the sensible universe], as far as he could, similarly perfect. The nature indeed of the animal itself was eternal, and this nature could not be entirely adopted into anything subject to generation; hence God resolved to form a certain movable image of eternity; and thus, while he was disposing the parts of the universe, he, out of that eternity which rests in unity, formed an eternal image on the NATURE 39 principle of numbers; and to this we give the appellation of Time." 1 This conception of time as the image of eternity Emerson lays down as the funda mental one in his Lecture on the Times. "The Times, as we say — or the present aspects of our social state, the Laws, Divinity, Natu ral Science, Agriculture, Art, Trade, Letters, have their root in an invisible spiritual real ity. To appear in these aspects, they must first exist, or have some necessary foundation. Beside all the small reasons we assign, there is a great reason for the existence of every extant fact; a reason which lies grand and immovable, often unsuspected, behind it in silence. The Times are the masquerade of the Eternities; trivial to the dull, tokens of noble and majestic agents to the wise ; the re ceptacle in which the Past leaves its history; the quarry out of which the genius of to-day is building up the Future." 2 Symbolism is an attempt to express the spiritual meaning of the world, to see in it a reflection of spiritual reality. It is a theory that appeals to the feeling for art, since the 1 The Tim&us, Bohn translation, II., 340-341. 2 Complete Works, I., 259. 40 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON world of things according to its teaching be comes an imitation of a spiritual world of pure intelligence. In Emerson's hands the theory assumes a literary value; and thus the end which nature serves when viewed sym bolically is called by him language. The final use which he makes of the theory does not appear in his Nature; there the theory is merely a stage through which he passes in his interpretation of the meaning of the universe. Later the same theory will reappear in his conception of art. A second theory of the meaning of nature is based upon the relation of the world of mat ter to the world of mind. This relation underlies symbolism; but in the new state ment which Emerson makes the terms are changed. Nature is conceived as an orderly system of laws executing themselves and mind is viewed as an invisible world in which ideas are the final realities. By correlating these two terms, the laws of nature and the ideas of the mind, Emerson gets his new theory. "The uneasiness which the thought of our helplessness in the chain of causes occasions us," he writes, "results from looking too much at one condition of nature, namely, Motion. But the drag is never taken from the wheel. NATURE 41 Wherever the impulse exceeds, the Rest or Identity insinuates its compensation. All over the wide fields of earth grows the pru nella or self-heal. After every foolish day we sleep off the fumes and furies of its hours; and though we are always engaged with par ticulars, and often enslaved to them, we bring with us to every experiment the innate uni versal laws. These, while they exist in the mind as ideas, stand around us in nature for ever embodied, a present sanity to expose and cure the insanity of men." 1 That is, laws of nature are correlative to ideas of mind. In such a theory the doctrine of ideas as set forth in Plato is apparent; but the form which the theory takes in Emerson is due to Coleridge's reworking of Plato's theory. Emerson himself has left a passage which proves this connection with Plato through Coleridge. "But the philosopher, not less than the poet," he explains in Nature, "post pones the apparent order and relations of things to the empire of thought. 'The prob lem of philosophy/ according to Plato, 'is, for all that exists conditionally, to find a ground unconditioned and absolute.' It pro ceeds on the faith that a law determines all 1 Complete Works, III., 194-195. 42 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON phenomena, which being known, the phe nomena can be predicted. That law, when in the mind, is an idea." 1 The source of this quotation is found in Coleridge's Friend, where the theory of cor relation was fully stated for Emerson: "The grand problem, the solution of which forms, according to Plato, the final object and dis tinctive character of philosophy, is this: for all that exists conditionally (that is, the ex istence of which is inconceivable except under the condition of its dependency on some other as its antecedent) to find a ground that is un conditional and absolute, and thereby to reduce the aggregate of human knowledge to a system. For the relation common to all being known, the appropriate orbit of each becomes discoverable, together with its pecul iar relations to its concentrics in the common sphere of subordination. Thus the centrality of the sun having been established, and the law of the distances of the planets from the sun having been determined, we possess the means of calculating the distance of each from the other. But as all objects of sense are in continual flux, and as the notices of them by the senses must, as far as they are true notices, ^Complete Works, I., 55. NATURE 43 change with them, while scientific principles or laws are no otherwise principles of science than as they are permanent and always the same, the latter were appropriated to the pure reason, either as its products or as implanted in it. And now the remarkable fact forces itself on our attention, namely, that the ma terial world is found to obey the same laws as had been deduced independently from the reason; and that the masses act by a force which can not be conceived to result from the component parts, known or imaginable. In magnetism, electricity, galvanism, and in chemistry generally, the mind is led instinct ively, as it were, to regard the working powers as conducted, transmitted, or accumulated by the sensible bodies, and not as inherent. This fact has, at all times, been the stronghold alike of the materialists and of the spiritual ists, equally solvable by the two contrary hypotheses, and fairly solved by neither. In the clear and masterly review of the elder philosophers, which must be ranked among the most splendid proofs of his judgment no less than of his genius, and more expressly in the critique on the atomic or corpuscular doc trine of Democritus and his followers as the one extreme, and in that of the pure rational- 44 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON ism of Zeno the Eleatic as the other, Plato has proved incontrovertibly that in both alike the basis is too narrow to support the super structure; that the grounds of both are false or disputable; and that if these were con ceded, yet neither the one nor the other scheme is adequate to the solution of the prob lem — namely, what is the ground of the coin cidence between reason and experience; or between the laws of matter and the ideas of the pure intellect. The only answer which Plato deemed the question capable of receiv ing, compels the reason to pass out of itself and seek the ground of this agreement in a supersensual essence, which being at once the ideal of the reason and the cause of the material world, is the pre-establisher of the harmony in and between both." * To make his statement clearer Coleridge adds in a note: "I now more especially en treat the reader's attention to the sense in which here, and everywhere through this essay, I use the word idea, I assert, that the very impulse to universalize any phenomenon involves the prior assumption of some efficient law in nature, which in a thousand different 1 The Friend. The Complete Works of Samuel Taylor Coleridge, II., 420-422. NATURE 45 forms is evermore one and the same, entire in each, yet comprehending all, and incapable of being abstracted or generalized from any number of phcenomena, because it is itself pre-supposed in each and all as their common ground and condition, and because every defi nition of a genus is the adequate definition of the lowest species alone, while the efficient law must contain the ground of all in all. It is attributed, never derived. The utmost we ever venture to say is, that the falling of an apple suggested the law of gravitation to Sir I. Newton. Now a law and an idea are correlative terms, and differ only as object and subject, as being and truth." 1 This is the manner in which Emerson con siders the question of nature. First in im portance of the influences upon the mind of the scholar is that of nature; and this influ ence, Emerson goes on to explain, leads the scholar to settle upon the value of nature to him, which is revealed only when he begins to study her meaning. "Classification be gins," Emerson says. "To the young mind every thing is individual, stands by itself. By and by, it finds how to join two things 1 The Friend. The Complete Works of Samuel Taylor Coleridge, II., 424. 46 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON and see in them one nature ; then three, then three thousand, and so, tyrannized over by its own unifying instinct, it goes on tying things together, diminishing anomalies, discovering roots running under ground whereby con trary and remote things cohere and flower out from one stem. . . . But what is classifi cation but the perceiving that these objects are not chaotic, and are not foreign, but have a law which is also a law of the human mind?" 1 Such correlation of nature and mind is everywhere present in Emerson's work: it is one of his fixed ideas. As a moralist he sees in the theory a proof of the essentially ethical character of all natural law. On this he insists. "The world is emblematic. Parts of speech are metaphors, because the whole of nature is a metaphor of the human mind. The laws of moral nature answer to those of matter as face to face in a glass. The visible world and the relation of its parts, is the dial plate of the invisible.' The axioms of physics translate the laws of ethics. Thus 'the whole is greater than its part;' 'reaction is equal to action;' 'the smallest weight may be made to lift the greatest, the difference of weight be- 1 Complete Works, I., 85-86. NATURE 47 ing compensated by time ;' and many the like propositions, which have an ethical as well as physical sense. These propositions have a much more extensive and universal sense when applied to human life, than when con fined to technical use." 1 This ethical interpretation of natural laws is a favorite exercise with Emerson. The specific instances of the correlation of mind and matter he calls "by-laws of the mind." a As example he dwells on the correspondence of gravity to truth. "The first quality we know in matter," he writes in explanation of the equivalence of the soul to nature, "is cen- trality — we call it gravity — which holds the universe together, which remains pure and indestructible in each mote as in masses and planets, and from each atom rays out illimita ble influence. To this material essence an swers Truth, in the intellectual world — Truth, whose center is everywhere and its circumference nowhere, whose existence we cannot disimagine; the soundness and health of things, against which no blow can be struck but it recoils on the striker; Truth, on whose side we always heartily are. And the first rf., I., 32-33. 2 Ibid., XII., 15. 48 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON measure of a mind is its centrality, its capac ity of truth, and its adhesion to it." 1 Other instances of analogies between the natural and the moral worlds are to be found in his paralleling diamagnetism, or cross magnetism, of gases with a law of personality which he calls bias.2 The chemical rule — corpora non agunt nisi soluta — he says holds true in mind.3 In fact, a long series of such analogies drawn from the laws of physics and vegetation constitutes a considerable part of what Emerson loves to call the Natural His tory of Intellect.4 The suggestion to gather such by-laws of the mind arose in Emerson's mind as a result of his reading in Bacon. Coleridge had placed Bacon side by side with Plato and had pointed out the relation of his natural phi losophy to Plato's system of ideas. Whether or not first directed to Bacon by Coleridge, Emerson certainly used Bacon in accordance with Coleridge's theory of correlation and came to associate Bacon's philosophy with that of Plato. 1 Complete Works, VIII., 221. 2 Ibid., VIIL, 306. ., XL, 533- ., XII., 23 et sq. NATURE 49 In his review of Bacon's work Emerson notes that Bacon "explained himself by giving various quaint examples of the summary or common laws of which each science has its own illustration." 1 This is a reference to a passage in the Advancement of Learning which Bacon cites in his explanation of the province of a First Philosophy. This phi losophy Bacon says is to be "a receptacle for all such profitable observations and axioms as fall not within the compass of any of the special parts of philosophy or sciences, but are more common and of a higher stage." 2 As instances of such observations and ax ioms he gives the following: "For example; is not the rule 'Si inasqualibus aequalia addas, omnia erunt inaequalia,' an axiom as well of justice as of mathematics? And is there not a true coincidence between commutative and distributive justice, and arithmetical and geo metrical proportion? Is not that other rule, 'Quae in eodem tertio conveniunt, et inter se conveniunt,' a rule taken from the mathe matics, but so potent in logic as all syllogisms are built upon it? Is not the observation, 'Omnia mutantur, nil interit,' a contempla- d., V., 240. 2 The Works of Francis Bacon, II., 126. 50 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON tion, in philosophy thus, that the quantum of nature is eternal? in natural theology thus, that it requireth the same omnipotence to make somewhat nothing, which at the first made nothing somewhat? according to the Scripture, 'Didici quod omnia opera, quae fecit Deus, perseverunt in perpetuum; non possumus eis quicquam addere nee auferre.' Is not the ground, which Machiavel wisely and largely discourseth concerning govern ments, that the way to establish and preserve them is to reduce them (ad principia,' a rule in religion and nature, as well as in civil ad ministration? Was not the Persian magic a reduction or correspondence of the principles and architectures of nature to the rules and policy of government? Is not the precept of a musician, to fall from a discord or harsh accord upon a concord or sweet accord, alike true in affection? Is not the trope of music, to avoid or slide from the close or cadence, common with the trope of rhetoric of deceiv ing expectation? Is not the delight of the quavering upon a stop in music the same with the playing of light upon the water? 'Splendet tremulo sub lumine pontus:' NATURE 51 Are not the organs of the senses of one kind with the organs of reflection, the eye with a glass, the ear with a cave or strait determined and bounded? Neither are those only simili tudes, as men of narrow observation may con ceive them to be, but the same footsteps of nature, treading or printing upon several subjects or matters. This science, therefore, as I understand it, I may justly report as de ficient; for I see sometimes the profounder sort of wits, in handling some particular argument, will now and then draw a bucket of water out of this well for their present use ; but the spring head thereof seemeth to me not to have been visited; being of so excellent use, both for the disclosing of nature, and the abridgement of art." 1 Emerson's by-laws of the mind are not so quaint, to use his own expression, as Bacon's, but they are open imitations of Bacon's man ner. They show how fruitful Coleridge's correlation of the Platonic and Baconian phi losophy was in suggesting to Emerson the practice of seeking the ethical meaning of the laws of nature. Emerson had no love of science in and for itself, but in the results of 1 The Works of Francis Bacon, II., 126-128. 52 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON science he found much to satisfy his spiritual needs when those results could be seen to have significance for morals. This means that Emerson held consistently to the sovereignty of ethics, by which he meant the supremacy of the moral or intel lectual world over the world of outward nature. Speaking of the laws of the natural world as perpetual forces, he says: "These forces are in an ascending series, but seem to leave no room for the individual ; man or atom, he only shares them; he sails the way these irresistible winds blow. But behind all these finer elements, the sources of them, and much more rapid and strong; a new style and series, the spiritual. Intellect and morals appear only the material forces on a higher plane. The laws of material nature run up into the invisible world of the mind, and hereby we acquire a key to those sublimities which skulk and hide in the caverns of human consciousness. And in the impenetrable mys tery which hides — and hides through absolute transparency — the mental nature, I await the insight which our advancing knowledge of material laws shall furnish." 1 By reason of Coleridge's correlation Em- 1 Complete Works, X., 72. NATURE 53 erson was able to speak of laws in the same manner as Plato treats ideas. These ideas of Plato's are the sole realities and they are known only by the intellect. They are grouped together in the intelligible world and, though they seem independent, there is one idea supreme among them. This is the idea of the Good. It is the chief end of all man's endeavors; the final satisfaction for which he strives. It is also the cause of ex istence to all things and of all knowledge that man can know. It is also the principle of unity both in the world of objective things and in the conscious life of intellect in man. Using the analogy of the sun in the visible world, Plato thus explains his conception: "That therefore which imparts truth to what is known, and dispenses the faculty of knowl edge to him who knows, you may call the idea of the good and the principle of science and truth, as being known through intellect. And as both these — knowledge and truth — are so beautiful, you will be right in thinking that the good is something different, and still more beautiful than these. Science and truth here are as light and sight there, which we rightly judged to be sun-like, but yet did not think them to be the sun: so here it is right 54 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON to hold that both of them partake of the form of the good, but yet not right to suppose that either of them is the good — inasmuch as the good itself is worthy of still greater honour. . . . You will say, I think, that the sun imparts to things which are seen, not only their visibility, but likewise their generation, growth and nourishment, though not itself generation? Of course. We may say, there fore, as to things cognizable by the intellect, that they became cognizable not only from the good, by which they are known, but likewise that their being and essence are thence de rived, while the good itself is not essence, but beyond essence, and superior to it both in dig nity and power." * Parallel to this conception is Emerson's idea of the universe. He believes in the real ity of an intelligible world, but it is a world of laws. And just as Plato had found the idea of the good giving unity to the ideas in the intelligible world, so Emerson finds uni versal good saturating all the laws of the universe and binding them into unity. "I find the survey of the cosmical powers a doc trine of consolation in the dark hours of private or public fortune. It shows us the 1 The Republic, Bohn translation, II., IQ&-I99. NATURE 55 world alive, guided, incorruptible; that its cannon cannot be stolen nor its virtues mis applied. It shows us the long Providence, the safeguards of rectitude. It animates ex ertion. . . . This world belongs to the energetical. It is a fagot of laws, and a true analysis of these laws, showing how immortal and how self-protecting they are, would be a wholesome lesson for every time and for this time. That band which ties them together is unity, is universal good, saturating all with one being and aim, so that each translates the other, is only the same spirit applied to new departments. Things are saturated with the moral law." 1 "It is essential to a true theory of nature and of man," says Emerson, "that it should contain somewhat progressive." 2 Holding to such a conception he was not at rest in stating the problem of nature until he had examined her method. Symbolism and correlation are the ories that account for the meaning of nature: they tell what she is ; but they do not let one into the secret of the life which gives nature her method. Therefore Emerson passes on to consider what this method of nature is; and 1 Complete Works, X., 85-86. 2 Ibid., I., 61. 56 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON he still finds in Platonism the suggestions for all his teachings on this new topic. At the basis of his thinking on the method of nature lies the doctrine of flux. This is an inheritance of Plato and the Platonists from the early philosophy of Heraclitus. As Soc rates remarks in the Gratylus, "Heracleitus says somewhere that all things move, and nothing is at rest; and comparing things to the flowing of a river, observes that 'Thou canst not twice into the same stream go.' " 1 Or, as Plotinus quotes Heraclitus, "bodies are always rising into existence, or becoming to be, and flowing." 2 This idea of flux Plato, and after him the Platonists, incorporated into their theory of the sensible world. In the Timceus the idea finds its fullest statement. "In the first place, then, what we now denomi nate water, on becoming condensed, seems to take the form of stones and earth, — and when melted and dispersed, that of vapour and air; air also when burnt up, becomes fire, while the latter again, on becoming condensed and extinct, resumes the form of air; and again air, when collected and condensed, produces 1 The Works of Plato, Bohn translation, III., 318. 2 Select Works of Plotinus, 276. NATURE 57 mists and clouds, from which, when still more compressed, rain descends; and from water again are formed earth and stones; the whole of them, as it seems, exchanging all round their mutual generation. "As these, then, never maintain any con stancy of existence, who will have the assur ance to maintain that any one of them is this rather than that? No one, and it would be far the safest plan to speak about them as fol lows: When we see anything constantly passing from one state of existence to another, as fire for instance, we should not say that it is fire absolutely, but something fiery — and again, that what we call water is not absolutely so, but something watery; without assigning to them any names that would give the idea of stability, as we think people do, when they express it by this and that; for not being of an abiding nature, it cannot endure to have applied to it such terms as, this thing, of this nature, belonging to this; and any such others as would show it to have a substantive exist ence. Hence we should not give anyone of them an individual name, but call it some thing such-like, but ever fluctuating; and es pecially with respect to fire, we should assert 58 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON that it is wholly such-like, and similarly like wise, everything endued with generation." 1 Emerson reflects this conception of the flux of things in his view of the eternal cycle of change manifested in the universe. "All things are flowing," he writes, "even those that seem immovable. The adamant is al ways passing into smoke. The plants imbibe the materials which they want from the air and the ground. They burn, that is, ex hale and decompose their own bodies into the air and earth again. The animal burns, or undergoes the like perpetual consumption. The earth burns, the mountains burn and de compose, slower, but incessantly. It is almost inevitable to push the generalization up into higher parts of Nature, rank over rank into sentient beings. Nations burn with eternal fire of thought and affection, which wastes while it works. We shall find finer combus tion and finer fuel. Intellect is a fire: rash and pitiless it melts this wonderful bone-house which is called man." 2 In this flux of things the constant substance is law. "Thin or solid, everything is in flight. I believe this conviction makes the charm of 1 The Works of Plato, Bohn translation, II., 355-356. 2 Complete Works, VII., 145. NATURE 59 chemistry — that we have the same avoirdu pois matter in an alembic, without a vestige of the old form; and in animal transforma tion not less, as in grub and fly, in egg and bird, in embryo and man; everything undress ing and stealing away from its old into new form, and nothing fast but those invisible cords which we call laws, on which all is strung. Then we see that things wear differ ent names and faces, but belong to one family; that the secret cords or laws show their well- known virtue through every variety, be it ani mal, or plant, or planet, and the interest is gradually transferred from the forms to the lurking method." l Such a view corresponds to Plato's reason ing from the instability of the flux of sensible things to the necessary existence of the idea, "which subsists according to sameness, unpro- duced and not subject to decay; receiving nothing into itself from elsewhere, and itself never entering into any other nature, but in visible and imperceptible by the senses, and to be apprehended only by pure intellect."2 The only variation to be noted is that Emer son makes law the permanent substance amid 1 Complete Works, VIII., 5. 2 The Timaus, Bohn translation, II., 358. 60 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON all change. But this had been made in ac cordance with Coleridge's statement of the re lation of the science of natural history to the science of intellect; they are correlative sciences and law which is the object of inquiry in the one is a correlative of idea, or the end of inquiry, in the other. By adopting this theory Emerson was able to restate the doc trine of flux in order to show that law is the only fixed thing we know in nature. But Emerson has another way of hand ling the idea of flux. Plotinus had used the doctrine to testify to the unreality of the world of sensible things as opposed to the reality of soul. Emerson follows him, as well as Plato; in fact, in his treatment of flux Emerson is more frequently following the ideas of Plotinus than of the older philosopher. For in Emerson the idea of flux is often associated with spirit or mind. Nature, he holds, is "always the effect, mind the flowing cause." 1 "Nature is not fixed but fluid. Spirit alters, moulds, makes it." 2 His treatment, then, leads to a discussion of the spiritual life of the universe which flows 1 Complete Works, VIIL, 223. 2 Ibid., I., 76. NATURE 61 through all things, animate and inanimate. The idea of flux is thus spiritualized. The simplest form his idea takes is given in his Two Rivers, in which he sets forth life as a flux. "Thy summer voice, Musketaquit, Repeats the music of the rain; But sweeter rivers pulsing flit Through thee, as thou through Concord Plain. "Thou in thy narrow banks are pent; The stream I love unbounded goes Through flood and sea and firmament, Through light, through life, it forward flows. "I see the inundations sweet, I hear the spending of the stream Through years, through men, through Nature fleet, Through love and thought, through power and dream. "Musketaquit, a goblin strong, Of shard and flint makes jewels gay; They lose their grief who hear his song, And where he winds is the day of day. 62 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON "So forth and brighter fares my stream — Who drink it shall not thirst again; No darkness stains its equal gleam, And ages drop in it like rain." 1 In setting forth this idea of flux in more de tail Emerson draws upon the doctrine of emanation as it was explained by Plotinus. Thus the flux of natural things becomes an emanation from a divine source. "The method of nature," he writes ; "who could ever analyze it? That rushing stream will not stop to be observed. We can never surprise nature in a corner; never find the end of a thread; never tell where to set the first stone. The bird hastens to lay her egg; the egg hastens to be a bird. The wholeness we ad mire in the order of the world is the result of infinite distribution. Its smoothness is the smoothness of the pitch of the cataract. Its permanence is a perpetual inchoation. Every natural fact is an emanation, and that from which it emanates is an emanation also, and from every emanation is a new emanation, If anything could stand still, it would be crushed and dissipated by the torrent it re sisted, and if it were a mind, would be crazed ; 1 Complete Works, IX., 248. NATURE 63 as insane persons are those who hold fast to one thought and do not flow with the course of nature. Not the cause, but an ever-novel effect, nature descends always from above. It is unbroken obedience. The beauty of these fair objects is imported into them from a metaphysical and eternal spring. In all animal and vegetable forms, the physiologist concedes that no chemistry, no mechanics, can account for the facts, but a mysterious princi ple of life must be assumed, which not only inhabits the organ but makes the organ." 1 Such an interpretation of the method of nature is a result of Emerson's reworking of the emanation theory of Plotinus in keeping with the primary notion of the flux of things. Instead of a ceaseless flux on a low plain of absolutely meaningless change, which the sim ple doctrine of flux amounts to, there is an endless flowing of things out of an eternal and metaphysical spring which is the divine source of all the fluxions. The latter concep tion finds its source in Plotinus' account of the emanation of things from the one absolute principle. "What, then," he writes of this principle, "shall we say he is? The power of all things, without whose subsistence the 1 Complete Works, I., 199-200. 64 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON universality of things would never have had a being; nor would intellect have been, which is the first and universal life; for that which subsists above life is the cause of life, since the energy of life which is all things, is not the first, but emanates this principle as its ineffa ble fountain. Conceive then a fountain pos sessing no other principle, but imparting itself to all rivers, without being exhausted by any one of them, and abiding quietly in itself; but the streams which emanate from this fountain, before they flow in different directions, as yet abiding together, and, as it were, already knowing what rivulets will proceed from their defluxions." * According to another way of viewing the subject the method of nature is identified with the manifestation of the divine Presence rush ing through the world in eternal progress. In such a conception the theory of evolution is felt but ancient philosophy still more. In Cudworth Emerson had noted an explanation of the universe conceived in the manner of the Platonists as TO TO*, or God. "TO nav, or 'the universe,' " says Cudworth, "was fre quently taken by the pagan theologers also, as we have already intimated, in a more com- 1 Five Books of Plotinus, 237. NATURE 65 prehensive sense, for the Deity, together with all the extent of its fecundity, God as display ing himself in the world; or, for God and the world both together; the latter being looked upon as nothing but an emanation or efflux from the former . . . And according to this sense was the god Pan understood both by the Arcadians and the other Greeks, not for the mere corporeal world as senseless and inanimate, nor as endued with a plastic na ture only (though this was partly included in the notion of Pan also), but as proceeding from a rational and intellectual principle, diffusing itself through all; or for the whole system of things, God and the world together, as one deity." 1 With this idea in mind Emerson has his pine tree sing of the method of nature: " 'Harken once more ! I will tell thee the mundane lore. Older am I than thy numbers wot, Change I may, but I pass not. Hitherto all things fast abide, And anchored in the tempest ride. Trenchant time behooves to hurry All to yean and all to bury: 1 The True Intellectual System of the Universe, I., 582. 66 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON All the forms are fugitive, But the substances survive. Ever fresh the broad creation, A divine improvisation, From the heart of god proceeds, A single will, a million deeds. Once slept the world an egg of stone, And pulse, and sound, and light was none; And God said, "Throb !" and then was motion And the vast mass became vast ocean. Onward and on, the eternal Pan, Who layeth the world's incessant plan, Halteth never in one shape, But forever doth escape, Like wave or flame, into new forms Of gems, and air, of plants, and worms. As the bee through the garden ranges, From world to world the godhead changes; As sheep go feeding in the waste, From form to form He maketh haste; This vault which glows immense with light Is the inn where he lodges for a night.' " 1 Finally, Emerson considers the flux of na ture as an indication of unfolding conscious ness of life. "If we look at her work," he writes of nature, "we seem to catch a glance 1 Complete Works, IX., 57-59. NATURE 67 of a system in transition. Plants are the young of the world, vessels of health and vigor; but they grope ever upward towards consciousness; the trees are imperfect men, and seem to bemoan their imprisonment, rooted in the ground. The animal is the novice and probationer of a more advanced order. The men, though young, having tasted the first drop from the cup of thought, are already dissipated: the maples and ferns are still uncorrupt; yet no doubt when they come to consciousness they too will curse and swear." 1 In thus explaining the method of nature Emerson was using a doctrine of Plotinus which taught the conscious life of contem plative activity in all things, even inanimate. "If previous to a serious inquiry into nature," he writes, "we should jocosely, as it were, affirm that all things desire contemplation, and verge to this as their end, not only rational animals but those destitute of reason, the na ture of plants, and earth, the mother of them all ; likewise that all things pursue contem plation, as far as the natural capacity of each permits, but that some things contemplate and pursue contemplation differently from others, 1 Complete Works, III., 181-182. 68 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON some in reality and some by imitation behold ing only the image; if we should affirm all this, shall we not appear to advance a doc trine entirely new?" 1 The method of nature in Emerson is thus one that grows out of a belief in the spiritual life of the universe. This life is set forth un der the figure of a stream. So Heraclitus had conceived it and had passed the idea down through Plato to the Platonists. In Emerson it is the characteristic image under which he views the life of the universe. But he is care ful to spiritualize the idea of a flux and to identify it with the ceaseless energy of the divine method in nature. Drawing upon the tenets of Platonism he presents this energy operating over and above things while seated in its divine source, or as immanent in nature as a rushing power of onward progress, or finally, as an unfolding consciousness of life. These are views of nature that identify her with spirit and as will appear later, it is into this that Emerson finally resolves the world of outward things. Universal antagonism is another idea under which Emerson views the life or method of 1 Five Books of Plotinus, 199-200. Cf. Complete Works of Ralph Waldo Emerson, L, 404. NATURE 69 nature. At times he considers the world a bifold fact made up of "metaphysical antag onists" 1 and names the dualism Undulation or Polarity.2 "Polarity, or action and reac tion, we meet in every part of nature," he explains; "in darkness and light; in heat and cold; in the ebb and flow of waters; in male and female; in the inspiration and expiration of plants and animals ; in the equation of quantity and quality in the fluids of the animal body; in the systole and diastole of the heart; in the undulations of fluids and of sound; in the centrifugal and centripetal gravity; in electricity, galvanism, and chemical affinity. Superinduce magnetism at one end of a needle, the opposite magnetism takes place at the other end. If the south attracts, the north repels. To empty here, you must condense there. An inevitable dualism bisects nature, so that each thing is a half, and suggests an other thing to make it whole; as, spirit, mat ter; man, woman; odd, even; subjective, ob jective; in, out; upper, under; motion, rest; yea, nay." 3 This is a development of the Pythagorean 1 Complete Works, I., 299. 2 Ibid., I., 98; II, 96. Ubid., II., 96-97. 70 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON notion which forms one phase of Emerson's Platonism. In De Gerando's Histoire Com- paree des Systemes de Philosophic Emerson found an account of the celebrated decade at tributed to Alcmaeon, which gives a list of couples constituting the universe. It groups the elements of the world into: "Le fini, Trepas, Finfini, aireipov, L'impair, Treptrrov, le pair, aprtov, L'un, ev, le multiple, ?rA^0os, Le droit, Se£tov, le gauche, apiorepov, Le male, appcv, le feminin, &?Av, L'objet en repos, ^pe/xwi/, en mouveau, Le direct, ev6v, le courbe, La lumiere, fas, les tenebres, Le bon, ayaOov, le mauvais, Le carre, rtrpaywov, le quadrilatere irregulier, In Emerson's series three of the original list of Alcmaeon appear; darkness and light, male and female; rest and motion. The ad ditions are his own and could be indefinitely extended, for the original scheme is arbitrary. It forms, however, the basis of all Emerson's thinking on this phase of nature. It is not as profoundly treated as the foregoing statement xi., 409- NATURE 71 of nature's method; it is a theory that moves on the surface of things and lacks deep insight into the inward life of nature. As applied to the world of morals it forms the ground of Emerson's law of compensation; but even when thus used, it yields to a higher idea grounded in a truer conception of the soul's life. Thus far nature has been viewed in its totality; but Emerson's philosophy attends to each particle of the mass and finds it repre sentative of the whole. He holds to "the fact that the universe is represented in every one of its particles. Everything in nature con tains all the powers of nature. Everything is made of one hidden stuff; as the naturalist sees one type under every metamorphosis, and regards a horse as a running man, a fish as a swimming man, a bird as a flying man, a tree as a rooted man. Each new form repeats not only the main character of the type, but part for part all the details, all the aims, further ances, hindrances, energies and whole system of every other. Every occupation, trade, art, transaction, is a compend of the world and a correlation of every other. Each is an entire emblem of human life; of its good and ill, its trials, its enemies, its course and its end. And 72 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON each one must somehow accommodate the whole man and recite all his destiny." * This is the doctrine of the microcosm as treated in the Platonists. In his Commen taries on the Timceus of Plato Proclus writes: aMan indeed is considered prior to all things, either because the theory respecting him per tains to us who make him the subject of dis cussion, and are ourselves men ; or because man is a microcosm, and all things subsist in him partially, as the world contains divinely and totally." 2 And in his On the Theology of Plato he applies the idea to each particle in the universe. "For if man is said to be a microcosm, is it not necessary that each of the elements by a much greater priority should contain in itself appropriately all that the world contains totally?" 3 Out of this conception arises Emerson's teaching of the fundamental unity in nature. "Herein is especially apprehended the unity of Nature — the unity in variety — which meets us everywhere. All the endless variety of things make an identical impression. Xeno- phanes complained in his old age, that, look 1 Complete Works, II., 101. 2 I, 4- 3 II., 193- NATURE 73 where he would, all things hastened back to Unity. He was weary of seeing the same entity in the tedious variety of forms. The fable of Proteus has a cordial truth. A leaf, a drop, a crystal, a moment of time, is related to the whole, and partakes of the perfection of the whole. Each particle is a microcosm, and faithfully renders the likeness of the world." 1 The same idea he expresses in his poem, Xenophanes. In thus insisting on the unity of things Emerson, as his reference shows, was using a fragment of ancient Hellenic thought with which he was familiar. He got his knowledge of Xenophanes in De Gerando, who says: "II [Xenophane] se plaignait que, dans les derniers temps de sa vie, il ne pouvait se feliciter de rien savoir avec certitude : 'quelque part qu'il portat ses regards, tout se resolvait pour lui dans 1'unite: il ne lui apparassait partout qu 'une substance semblable a elle- meme.' " 2 In the conception of the unity of all things, so Emerson teaches, lies the possibility of re storing nature to its original and eternal beauty. As long as nature is studied in a nar- 1 Complete Works, I., 43. 2Histoire Comparee des Systemes de Philosophic, I., 460. 74 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON rowly scientific spirit which attends primarily to naming of individual species, nature will never reveal her true meaning to the mind of man. Thus in his poem, Blight, he expresses his weariness of a surface knowledge of things and accuses the young scholars of a lack of love and therefore of the mystic knowledge of the flowers they pick. His mind refreshes itself in the thought of the old students of na ture. "The old men studied magic in the flowers, And human fortunes in astronomy, And an omnipotence in chemistry, Preferring things to names, for these were men, Were Unitarians of the united world, And, wheresoever their clear eye-beams fell, They caught the footsteps of the Same." l That is, the old men held to a conception of a unity of things which subsisted the same throughout all diversity. But we, he adds, are strangers to the stars, the beast, the bird, the mine, and the plant because we use them for selfish gain and do not ask their love. "Therefore, to our sick eyes, The stunted trees look sick, the summer short, 1 Complete Works, IX., 140. NATURE 75 Clouds shade the sun, which will not tan our hay, And nothing thrives to reach its natural term." 1 To bring back original beauty to the world thus blighted, the soul of man should cease from its disunited life and live in a divine unity. "The problem of restoring to the world original and eternal beauty is solved by the redemption of the soul. The ruin or the blank that we see when we look at nature, is in our own eye. The axis of vision is not co incident with the axis of things, and so they appear not transparent but opaque. The rea son why the world lacks unity, and lies broken and in heaps, is because man is dis united with himself. He cannot be a natural ist until he satisfies all the demands of the spirit. Love is as much its demand as per ception. Indeed, neither can be perfect with out the other . . . When a faithful thinker, resolute to detach every object from personal relations and see it in the light of thought, shall, at the same time, kindle science with the fire of the holiest affections, then will God go forth anew into the creation." 2 This enkindling of the intellect by love is the distinguishing characteristic of the spirit 141. Ibid., I, 73-74. 76 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON of inquiry in Plato. The true philosopher ac cording to him is above all things a lover of truth. And this conception is carried over into the scheme of the Platonists, who make the highest end of all human knowledge the vision of the eternal unity of all things, the One. Thus Proclus explains that the mania, or the inspiration belonging to the lover, "re ceiving the soul united, conjoins this one of the soul to the gods, and to intelligible beauty." l That is, by living with a divine unity the soul realizes the highest possible experience. And this according to Emerson would mean the re-creation of the world. Hence in the closing section of Nature, "Prospects," he turns to the need of re-creating the world as the prospect that lies before each one after he has come to understand the meaning of nature and its relation to the mind of man. But at this point Emerson's thought passes over to a consideration of his second great theme, soul : and hence the final solution of the meaning of nature cannot be arrived at until this theme has been carefully explained. 1 Quoted by lamblichus, On the Mysteries, 356. CHAPTER III SOUL THROUGHOUT his treatment of nature Emerson relates his subject to soul. His themes of symbolism and correlation of mind and matter recognized the dependence of nature upon spirit or mind. His concep tion of the method of nature leads him to maintain the divine character of the energy which nature reveals in ceaseless operation in her realm. And his hope of the restoration of nature to her primary and eternal beauty is based upon his belief in the purification of the soul as the means to effect the change. It was natural, then, as he was at work on his first book, Nature, that he should have contemplated the writing of another essay which he was to entitle Spirit. His plan as later developed did not, however, assign this new idea to a second essay but found a place for it in the original work. The seventh chapter of Nature is thus entitled "Spirit," the theme of which is indicated in its opening 77 78 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON paragraph: "And all the uses of nature ad mit of being summed in one, which yields the activity of man an infinite scope. Through all its kingdoms, to the suburbs and outskirts of things, it is faithful to the cause whence it had its origin. It always speaks of Spirit." 1 In Emerson's conception of spirit, then, is to be found his final teaching on the meaning of existence; in revealing the nature of soul all his deepest thinking ends. His favorite authors were rich in schemes of speculation on this subject. Plato had placed the metaphysics of the soul on a commanding eminence in his Phcedo, Phcedrus, Republic and Timceus. Plotinus had left a group of Enneads that carried the speculations of Plato into the high realm of rational mysticism in which the soul of man is in actual contact with the soul of the highest principle of all things, the One; and in his theories of a universal In tellect and a Soul of the Universe he had given the form for all the speculation of the Plato- nists on the nature of soul. The attention which Emerson gave to such speculation even in its most mystical flights testifies to the close ness and the sympathy with which he read his Platonic sources. 1 Complete Works, I., 61. SOUL 79 Soul in Emerson is an all-embracing term. It means God. It is also conceived as an in tellectual energy, or pure intellect. And at times Emerson conceives it as the very life of the universe under the form of a world soul. Roughly speaking, his division corresponds to the three principles of the Platonists which are often spoken of as the Platonic trinity — the One, Universal Intellect, and Universal Soul. These three are conceived as the ab solute hypostases of things and are all found in the soul of man. Emerson thus was able to dignify his conception of the human soul by relating it to these great principles. Of psychology in the scientific acceptance of the term in present-day philosophy Emerson has practically nothing to say; but of Soul as a divine presence in man and the universe he has left much in his most characteristic work. Owing to his teachings on this subject he has come to be regarded as a seer and out of his central conception arises the great power which his writings generate in the lives of his readers. In order to show the importance of Platonism in his doctrine of the soul, then, it will be best to follow the threefold division of his idea: Soul as God, or the Over-Soul; 8o THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON Soul as Intellect; and Soul in the universe, or the World-Soul. I. THE OVER-SOUL. The ground of all his teaching on soul is to be found in his doctrine of a Universal Mind, which is the sovereign agent common in its entirety to all men. "There is one mind," so his statement runs, "common to all individual men. Every man is an inlet to the same and to all of the same. He that is once admitted to the right of reason is made a freeman of the whole estate. What Plato has thought, he may think; what a saint has felt, he may feel; what at any time has befallen any man, he can understand. Who hath access to this univer sal mind is a part to all that is or can be done, for this is the only and sovereign agent." 1 In Cudworth is found a conception quite similar to this of Emerson's. To confute the theories of atheism Cudworth lays down the principle "that there can be but one only orig inal mind, or no more than one understanding Being self-existent; all other minds whatso ever partaking of one original mind; and be- 1 Complete Works, II., 3. THE OVER-SOUL 81 ing, as it were, stamped with the impression or signature of one and the same seal. From whence it cometh to pass, that all minds, in the several places and ages of the world, have ideas or notions of things exactly alike, and truths indivisibly the same. Truths are not multiplied by the diversity of minds that ap prehend them ; because they are all but ectypal participations of one and the same original or archetypal mind and truth. As the same face may be reflected in several glasses; and the image of the same sun may be in a thousand eyes at once beholding it; and one and the same voice may be in a thousand ears listening to it; so when innumerable created minds have the same ideas of things, and understand the same truths, it is but one and the same eternal light that is reflected in them all ("that light, which enlighteneth every man that cometh into the world"), or the same voice of that one everlasting Word, that is never silent, re echoed by them." * The conception of a universal mind goes back to the Neo-Platonic doctrine of one su preme intellect. In this mind all particular minds are contained, each expressing the whole in its own way. This supreme intellect 1 The True Intellectual Systems of the Universe, III., 71. 82 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON is one of the absolute principles. An account of the manner in which all minds exist in this one great mind is found in Plotinus. "They likewise see all things, not those with which generation, but those with which essence is present. And they perceive themselves in others. For all things there are diaphanous; and nothing is dark and resisting, but every thing is apparent to every one internally and throughout. For light everywhere meets with light; since everything contains all things in itself, and again sees all things in another. So that all things are everywhere, and all is all. Each thing likewise is everything." 1 Emerson's account compared with Cud- worth's and Plotinus' shows a characteristic manner of approach. Cudworth and Plotinus are concerned with the nature and existence of the supreme mind considered in and for it self, while Emerson views the question from the standpoint of the individual man who shares in this supreme mind as an inherited right. He thus emphasizes the individual's claim to such a mind. But Emerson elaborates the idea in an even more characteristic fashion. In the state ment of the doctrine as thus far made, the 1 Select Works, Introduction, p. Ixxx., note. THE OVER-SOUL 83 universal mind is described as merely present to each individual ; no more specific account of the relation between the two is given. But in the name Over-Soul, which Emerson ap plies to the universal mind, there is a clear in dication of a change in the relation between it and the individual; the universal soul pre sides over the former, gives it its life and directs its energies. This advance in the idea recognizes the teaching of the Platonists concerning the in ter-relation of their three great principles of all things. These principles are arranged in a causal series. At the head is the One, out of which proceeds logically Universal Mind or Intellect; and this latter in turn gives rise to Universal Soul. Each of the two princi ples below the One finds above it a greater principle out of which it comes and toward which its energies are directed. Proclus speaking of the relation of the third princi ple to the second says that "she [soul] sees above all souls, intellectual essences and or ders. For above every soul a deiform intel lect resides, which imparts to the soul an in tellectual habit. She also sees prior to these, the monads of the gods themselves which are above intellect, and from which the intellec- 84 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON tual multitudes receive their unions. For it is necessary that unific causes should be placed above things united, in the same manner as vivifying causes are above things vivified, causes that impart intellect are above things intellectualized, and in a similar manner un- participable hypostases are above all partici pants." x Plotinus, in like manner, describes the relation of soul to the world. "For it [soul] governs, abiding on high. And the world is animated after such a manner, that it cannot with so much propriety be said to have a soul of its own, as to have a soul presiding over it; being subdued by, and not subduing it, and being possessed, and not possessing. For it lies in soul which sustains it, and no part of it is destitute of soul ; being moistened with life, like a net in water." 2 In such statements as these is to be found the suggestion of that theory of the Over-Soul which Emerson expounds in the following passage: "The Supreme Critic on the errors of the past and the present, and the only prophet of that which must be, is that great 1 Proclus, On Providence and Fate, in On the Theology of Plato, II., 455-456. 2 Select Works, 343. THE OVER-SOUL 85 nature in which we rest as the earth lies in the soft arms of the atmosphere; that Unity, that Over-Soul, within which every man's particular being is contained and made one with all other; that common heart of which all sincere conversation is the worship, to which all right action is submission ; that over powering reality which confutes our tricks and talents, and constrains every one to pass for what he is, and to speak from his character and not from his tongue, and which evermore tends to pass into our thought and hand and become wisdom and virtue and power and beauty. We live in succession, in division, in parts, in particles. Meantime within man is the soul of the whole; the wise silence; the universal beauty, to which every part and particle is equally related; the eternal One." J In this passage there is an accumulation of detail which shows how Emerson uses the various doctrines of Platonism to do honor to his great idea, the Over-Soul. He identifies it with "that Unity" and with "the eternal One," both of which expressions refer to the first of the absolute principles of the Platon- ists, the One. In stating that in the Over- Soul every man's particular being is contained 1 Complete Works, II., 26^-269. 86 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON and made one with all other, he makes refer ence to the conception of the supreme intellect, in which, according to Plotinus, all minds subsist together. "And they perceive them selves in others," Plotinus writes. "For all things there are diaphanous; and nothing is dark and resisting, but everything is apparent to everyone internally and throughout. For light everywhere meets with light; since everything contains all things in itself, and again sees all things in another. So that all things are everywhere, and all is all. Each thing likewise is everything." 1 When he says that though we live in di vision, there is within us the soul of the whole, his words recall what Plotinus had written of the soul: "For it does not give life to individuals, through a division of itself into minute parts, but it vivifies all things with the whole of itself; and the whole of it is present everywhere, in a manner similar to its gen erator, both according to oneness and ubiq uity." 2 In identifying the Over-Soul with the universal beauty, Emerson is referring to the absolute beauty which stands at the end of the dialectic quest in Plato's Banquet and 1 Select Works, Introduction, p. Ixxx., note. 2 Ibid., 258. THE OVER-SOUL 87 which Plotinus at times acknowledges to be the first principle of things, the beautiful itself.1 Furthermore, in designating the Over- Soul "the wise silence," Emerson was but summing up what Plotinus teaches concern ing the One and its knowledge of itself. "In the next place," adds Plotinus, "that which is entirely simple will not be in want of a busy energy, as it were, about itself. For what will it learn by intellectual perception? For prior to this perception, it exists that which it is to itself. For again, knowledge is a cer tain desire and, as it were, an investigating discovery. Hence, that which is without any difference in itself with respect to itself, is quiescent, and investigates nothing respecting itself." 2 It is so truly one that it does not even think itself and yet is not ignorant. Finally, in stating that this Over-Soul is within us, Emerson agrees with Plotinus in his explanation that "as in the nature of things there are these three hypostases, so, likewise, it is proper to think, that the above mentioned three subsist with us." 3 Emerson's exposi- 1 An Essay on the Beautiful, 32. 2 Select Works, 432. 9 Ibid., 279. 88 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON tion, then, of the Over-Soul is a highly concen trated series of Platonic conceptions, whose central life is to be found in the theorizing of Plotinus concerning the One. No better illustration of the way in which Emerson uses the shreds and patches of Platonic theory to express himself could be found. In Emerson's most characteristic teaching, then, soul is conceived in a way that lifts it above the common view of its nature as the mere thinking and vital part of man. It is not a faculty. It is rather the Divine Pres ence itself in man striving to burn away all that is personal, so that He alone can give life to the individual soul. In this Divine Soul man participates; it is a larger thing than any one soul, so to speak, for it is the Over-Soul. Thus Emerson in his essay, The Over-Soul, at the outset of his explanation carefully defines his idea: "All goes to show that the soul in man is not an organ, but animates and exer cises all the organs ; is not a function, like the power of memory, of calculation, of compari son, but uses these as hands and feet; is not a faculty, but a light; is not the intellect or the will, but the master of the intellect or the will ; is the background of our being, in which they lie — an immensity not possessed and cannot V THE OVER-SOUL 89 be possessed. From within or from behind, a light shines through us upon things and makes us aware that we are nothing, but the light is alJU'LA. Such psychology is in keeping with the con ception of Plotinus. From Plato, Plotinus inherited the manner of conceiving spiritual notions under the figure of light. The part that the figure plays in his explanation of the mystical experiences of the soul is an impor tant one. Thus he speaks of the mystical trance when the soul enjoys the presence of the One : "Then also it is requisite to believe that we have seen it, when the soul receives a sudden light. For this light is from him, and is him. And then it is proper to think that he is present, when like another God entering into the house of some one who in vokes him, he fills it with splendour. For unless he entered, he would not illuminate it. And thus the soul would be without light, and without the possession of this God. But when illuminated, it has that which it sought for. This likeness is the true end to the soul, to come into contact with his light, and to behold him through it; not by the light of another thing; but to perceive that very thing itself 1 Complete Works, II., 270. 90 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON through which it sees. For that through which it is illuminated, is the very thing which it is necessary to behold." 1 Emerson's account shows a direct connec tion with one of the Cambridge Platonists, John Smith, an extract from whose work ap pears in a note to a passage in Coleridge's Aids to Reflection. To point the difference between reason and understanding Coleridge quotes from Smith's Posthumous Tracts ( 1660) : " 'While we reflect on our own idea of Reason, we know that our souls are not it, but only partake of it; and that we have it Kara pAOgw and not K°-T oixnrjv. Neither can it be called a faculty, but far rather a light, which we enjoy, but the source of which is not in ourselves, nor rightly by any individual to be denominated mine! " 2 It is a concep tion of soul quite in keeping with Plotinus' conception and so tersely stated as to attract Emerson. Holding to such a conception of soul, Plotinus finds the highest experience possible for man in a mystical state. Plato had never developed the mystical side of his doctrine as 1 Select Works, 452-453. 2 The Complete Works of Samuel Taylor Coleridge, I., 264, n. THE OVER-SOUL 91 it lay inherent in his conception of an abso lute idea of the good which is above all being. Now the all-absorbing work of Plotinus was to formulate a scheme of mysticism on the basis of Plato. In so doing he brought to a logical culmination the preceding develop ment of all Hellenic thought so that his work stands to-day as the flower of that philosophi cal life which started with Thales and Anaxi- mander. His system is thus one of rational mysticism, which aims to show how the log ical outcome of speculation on knowledge ends in an experience which transcends knowl edge itself. Such a scheme appealed to Emerson ; it was as the water of life to his soul. His demand was for a philosophy of insight. He was dis satisfied with the ways of systematic philoso phy; what he wanted above all things was a fresh contact with spiritual realities. "The foregoing generations beheld God and nature face to face; we, through their eyes. Why should not we also enjoy an original relation to the universe? Why should not we have a poetry and philosophy of insight and not of tradition, and a religion by revelation to us, and not the history of theirs?" 1 The mystical 1 Complete Works, L, 3. 92 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON teaching of Plotinus satisfied these needs, as will appear when Emerson's work is reviewed in connection with the Enneads of Plotinus and other writings of members of his school. Both Emerson and Plotinus agree in defin ing the mystic state as a union of the soul with God. "Ineffable is the union of man and God," writes Emerson, "in every act of the soul. The simplest person who in his integ rity worships God, becomes God." 1 In his account of the experience Plotinus says of the soul: "Becoming wholly absorbed in deity, she is one, conjoining as it were centre with centre. For here concurring they are one; but they are then two when they are separate. . . . Since, therefore [in this conjunction with deity], there were not two things, but the perceiver was one with the thing per ceived, as not being [properly speaking] vision, but union ; whoever becomes one by mingling with deity, and afterwards recol lects this union, will have with himself an image of it." 2 Both describe the experience as a vision in which the two participants are one. Writing of the eternal One present in the soul of man, 1 Ibid., II., 292. 2 Select Works, 502-503. THE OVER-SOUL 93 Emerson states as the peculiarity of the ex perience that "the act of seeing and the thing seen, the seer and the spectacle, the subject and the object are one." * A like characteris tic is put forward by Plotinus. "Perhaps, however, neither must it be said that he sees, but that he is the thing seen ; if it is necessary to call these two things, i. e., the perceiver and the thing perceived. But both are one; though it is bold to assert this." 2 Examined from another point of view, the relation is not thus boldly stated, but is changed to one in which the soul of the indi vidual is enveloped by an all-embracing pres ence. In lamblichus the contact with divinity is thus given: "We are comprehended in it, or rather we are filled by it, and we possess that very thing which we are [or by which our essence is characterized], in knowing the gods." 3 In recounting his experience when the soul opens to a vision of the unity of things Emerson says of the beatitude: "It is not in us so much as we are in it." 4 He repeats the idea in the same account.5 Speaking of mo- 1 Complete Works, II., 269. 2 Select Works, 502. 3 On the Mysteries, 24. 4 Complete Works, VI., 25. 5 Ibid., VI., 26. 94 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON ments of inspiration, Emerson uses the same form of statement — "We might say of these memorable moments of life that we were in them, not they in us." 1 It is a common ex pression with him. In one of the Chaldean oracles the idea of envelopment is conveyed in a slightly varied form which Emerson also uses. Speaking of human souls, the oracle explains: "But they lie in God, drawing vigorous torches [i. e., unities, images of the one~\, descending from the father; and from these descending, the soul plucks of empyrean fruits, the soul- nourishing flower." 2 In language less tech nical and figurative Emerson conveys the thought underlying this oracle in his words — "We lie in the lap of immense intelligence, which makes us receivers of its truth and organs of its activity." 3 Emerson even imitates perhaps the most impressive account which Plotinus has left of the experience. In one of his descriptions Plotinus closes with the conclusion — "This, therefore, is the life of the Gods, and of divine and happy men, a liberation from all terrene 1 Complete Works, VIII., 279. 2 Select Works, 343, note i. 3 Complete Works, II., 64. THE OVER-SOUL 95 concerns, a life unaccompanied with human pleasures, and a flight of the alone to the alone." 1 Such an experience Emerson calls "a beatitude, but without any sign of joy; earnest, solitary, even sad." 2 And quoting Plotinus, he names it "the flight of the alone to the alone."* Consequently, in his Over- Soul he emphasizes the necessity of loneliness, of the putting away of all human mediation as the condition of the experience. "The soul gives itself, alone, original and pure, to the Lonely, Original and Pure, who, on that con dition, gladly inhabits, leads and speaks through it." 4 The loneliness and sadness of the flight im pressed him as is seen in his more elaborate attempt to bring out the unique character of the experience. "And now at last," he writes, "the highest truth on this subject remains un said; probably cannot be said; for all that we say is the far-off remembering of the intuition. That thought by what I can now nearest ap proach to say it, is this. When good is near you, when you have life in yourself, it is not by any known or accustomed way; you shall 1 Select Works, 506. 2 Complete Works, IV., 97. 3 Ibid. *Ibid., II., 296. 96 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON not discern the footprints of any other; you shall not see the face of man; you shall not hear any name; — the way, the thought, the good, shall be wholly strange and new. It shall exclude example and experience. You take the way from man, not to man. All per sons that ever existed are its forgotten minis ters. Fear and hope are alike beneath it. There is somewhat low even in hope. In the hour of vision there is nothing that can be called gratitude, nor properly joy." 1 The note of loneliness in Plotinus' descrip tion of the mystic trance caught Emerson's ear and awakened a response within him. He loved solitude for the spiritual strengthening he found in it; and throughout his work he lays emphasis upon the need of it in life. "Ah me!" he complains, "no man goeth alone."2 "Let me admonish you," he says to the Cam bridge divinity students, "first of all, to go alone." 3 To gain self-reliance he says, "We must go alone."4 "Think alone," he holds, "and all places are friendly and sacred." 5 Of the poets who live as hermits in cities he 1 Complete Works, II., 68-69. 2 Ibid., I, 144. 3 Ibid., I., 145. * Ibid., II., 71. * Ibid., I., 174. THE OVER-SOUL 97 writes : "They are alone with the mind." l In all these sentences is heard the echoing of that phrase of Plotinus which names the mys tic experience "a flight of the alone to the alone." In teaching receptivity as the attitude of the soul in this experience Emerson identifies himself with Plotinus. The latter held athat the nature of soul is everywhere tractable; and that it may be received the most easily of all things, if any thing is fashioned so as to be passive to it, and is able to receive a certain portion of it." 2 The same idea is given in Emerson's words : "When I watch that flow ing river, which, out of regions I see not, pours for a season its streams into me, I see that I am a pensioner; not a cause but a surprised spec tator of this ethereal water; that I desire and look up and put myself in the attitude of re ception, but from some alien energy the vis ions come." 3 Before such a mystic experience is possible there must be a putting off of all that is for eign so as to present the soul in pure naked ness. Thus Plotinus speaking of such abla- *Ibid., I., 175- * Select Works, 347. 3 Complete Works, II., 268. 98 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON tion remarks: "But as it is said of matter, that it ought to be void of all qualities, in or der that it may receive the impressions of all things; thus also, and in a much greater de gree, it is necessary that the soul should be come formless, in order that there may be no impediment to its being filled and illuminated by the first principles of things." 1 "And how, therefore," he asks, "can this be accom plished? By an ablation of all things." 2 In such teaching we find the parallel to Emer son's reiterations of the necessity of humility as a condition of the mystic experience; as when he assures us : "This energy does not descend into individual life on any other con dition than entire possession. It comes to the lowly and simple; it comes to whomsoever will put off what is foreign and proud." 3 A second condition of enjoying the great experience is that the soul should be in a state of absolute oneness. As Plotinus puts it, "the soul, likewise, should for this purpose be liberated from all vice, in consequence of has tening to the [vision of the] good; and should ascend to the principle which is in herself, and 1 Select Works, 491. 2 Ibid., 454. 8 Complete Works, II., 289. THE OVER-SOUL 99 become one instead of many things, in order that she may survey the principle of all things, and the one/' l Or, as Emerson says of one who reverences the soul, "he will weave no longer a spotted life of shreds and patches, but he will live with a divine unity." 2 In this unified life, as has already been seen, Emerson finds the way to restore the world to its orig inal beauty. The feeling experienced by the soul in this union with the divine One is a nimble glad ness. According to Plotinus when the soul sees God, "she will perceive herself to be a pure light, unburthened, agile." 3 "She is affected in the most felicitous manner." 4 Or as Emerson describes the feeling of the soul, "then is it glad, young and nimble." 5 The element of youthfulness in Emerson's statement was imported into the experience from a source other than Plotinus: it is a sug gestion from Proclus. In his own copy of Proclus On the Theology of Plato Emerson had indexed under "Youth" a passage from which the following is an extract: "For he 1 Select Works, 476. 2 Complete Works, II., 297. 3 Select Works, 500. * Ibid., 499. 5 Complete Works, II., 296. ioo THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON [Plato] says that souls in the Saturnian period abandon old age, but return to youth, and re move from themselves hoariness but have black hair; but the cheeks of those that have beards being rendered smooth, they are re stored to the past season (of youth)."1 In like vein Emerson writes : "We grizzle every day. I see no need of it. Whilst we con verse with what is above us, we do not grow old, but grow young. Infancy, youth, recep tive, aspiring, with religious eye looking up ward, counts itself nothing and abandons it self to the instruction flowing from all sides. But the man and woman of seventy assume to know all, they have outlived their hope, they renounce aspiration, accept the actual for the necessary and talk down to the young. Let them then become organs of the Holy Ghost; let them be lovers ; let them behold truth ; and their ever are uplifted, their wrinkles smoothed, they are perfumed again with hope and power." 2 In spite of the attempt to describe the state, its ineffableness remains its chief feature. After his account of the union, Plotinus adds: "This spectacle is a thing difficult to explain 1 1, 333- 2 Complete Works, II., 319. THE OVER-SOUL 101 by words. For how can any one narrate that as something different from himself, which, when he sees he does not behold as different, but as one with himself? This, therefore, is manifested by the mandate of the mysteries, which orders that they shall not be divulged to those who are uninitiated. For as that which is divine cannot be unfolded to the mul titude, this mandate forbids the attempt to elucidate it to any one but him who is for tunately able to perceive it." * Similar to this are the utterances of Emerson: "I can not — nor can any man — speak precisely of things so sublime, but it seems to me the wit of man, his strength, his grace, his tendency, his art, is the grace and the presence of God. It is beyond explanation." 2 "Ineffable is the union of man and God in every act of the soul. The simplest person who in his integrity wor ships God, becomes God; yet for ever and ever the influx of this better and universal self is new and unsearchable." 3 The absolute principle with which the soul aims to identify itself is also ineffable. "There is a principle \vhich is the basis of 1 Select Works, 502-503. 2 Complete Works, L, 194. 3 Ibid.. II., 292. 102 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON things," observes Emerson, "which all speech aims to say, and all action to evolve, a simple, quiet, imdescribed, undescribable presence, dwelling very peacefully in us, our rightful lord." l Plotinus names the One "the most simple of things." "Being alone and soli tary," he adds, "it is perfectly quiescent." 2 He further observes: "Hence, it is in reality ineffable. For of whatever you speak, you speak of a certain thing. But of that which is beyond all things, and which is beyond even most venerable intellect, it is alone true to assert that it has not any other name [than the ineffable], and that it is not some one of all things. Properly speaking, however, there is no name of it, because nothing can be asserted of it. We, however, endeavour as much as possible to signify to ourselves something re specting it." 3 Entrance into this high communion is not by knowledge or any reasoning process, but by an actual presence of the great principle in the soul of man. "In this affair," writes Plotinus, "a doubt especially arises, because the perception of the highest God is not ef- * Ibid., VI., 213. 2 Select Works, 441, 429. ., 439- THE OVER-SOUL 103 fected by science, nor by intelligence, like other intelligibles, but by the presence of him, which is a mode of knowledge superior to that of science. But the soul suffers an apostacy from the one, and is not entirely one when it receives scientific knowledge. For science is reason, and reason is multitudinous. The soul, therefore, in this case, deviates from the one, and falls into number and multitude." l In keeping with such an idea Emerson writes: "If we ask whence this comes, if we seek to pry into the soul that causes, all philos ophy is at fault. Its presence or its absence is all we can affirm." 2 Man attempting to give an account of himself must be content to re cite "the fact that there is a Life not to be described or known otherwise than by posses sion. What account can he give of his essence more than so it was to be? The royal reason, the Grace of God, seems the only description of our multiform, but ever identical fact. There is virtue, there is genius, there is success, or there is not. There is the incoming or the receding of God : that is all we can affirm ; and we can show neither how nor why." 3 1 Select Works, 479. 2 Complete Works, II., 65. 8 Ibid., I., 204. 104 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON Such parallelisms of thought and at times of language strengthen the belief in the indebt edness of Emerson to Plotinus' account of philosophic mysticism. But such indebted ness does not preclude the genuineness of Em erson's own experience. His mind was in constant tension in the endeavor to describe its own feelings; and to no experience does he more often refer than to the divine moments of intuition. The range of the intuition is a wide one; it embraces at its highest ecstasy, trance, and prophetic inspiration, and at its lowest "the faintest glow of virtuous emo tion." 1 In recording this milder form of the experience Emerson was but describing his own psychological states, but into his ac count he imports many facts which Plotinus had recorded. And in a degree, impossible now to indicate, Emerson made them facts of his own experience. It was his way to live out his teachings before he proclaimed them. Still the record reveals the traces of his read ing and study. A good instance of this blend of alien thought with his own experience is to be found in a personal feeling which he enjoyed in the presence of certain aspects of nature. "Starid- 1 Complete Works, II., 281. THE OVER-SOUL 105 ing on the bare ground," he tells us, "my head bathed by the blithe air and uplifted into in finite space — all mean egotism vanishes. I become a transparent eyeball; I am nothing; I see all ; the currents of the Universal Being circulate through me; I am part or parcel of God. The name of the nearest friend sounds then foreign and accidental: to be brothers, to be acquaintances, master or servant, is then a trifle and a disturbance. I am the lover of uncontained and immortal beauty." 1 In this passage there are characteristic recollections of Platonic and Plotinic concep tions. The most startling expression — "I be come a transparent eyeball" — is a rendering of a sentiment Emerson had noted in Plotinus, who, in order to describe the manner of knowledge in the intelligible world, writes : "There, however, everybody is pure, and each inhabitant is, as it were, an eye. Nothing likewise is there concealed, or fictitious, but before one can speak to another, the latter knows what the former intended to say." 2 The identification of himself in part with God is in keeping with what has already been said of the complete union of the soul with the 1 Complete Works, I., 10. 2 Select Works, 365. io6 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON One. The fact that he is "the lover of uncon- tained and immortal beauty" recalls Plato's description of the idea of beauty as given in the Banquet: "It exists forever, being neither produced nor destroyed, and neither suffering increase nor decay . . . nor does it exist in any other being, such as an animal ; nor in the earth, nor in the heavens, nor in any other part of the universe ; but it subsists by and with itself, and possesses a form eternally one." 1 A more vital use of the doctrines of Platon- ism is found in Emerson's application of them to the realm of conduct. Among the ethical ideals which he sets forth self-reliance is cen tral. It is central because it is a deduction from the reality of the mystical experience in the soul. The essence of that state lies in the identification of the soul with the Divine; the soul shares the power of the Divine; it is strong with the same strength. And the chief characteristic of the divine One, according to Plotinus, is its self-sufficiency; it is in need of nothing, but exists alone in itself. "That which is perfectly simple," says Plotinus of the One, "and truly self-sufficient, is not in want of any thing." 2 "For it does not seek 1 Bohn translation, III., 552-553- 2 Select Works, 440. THE OVER-SOUL 107 after any thing in order that it may be, nor in order that it may be in an excellent condition, nor that it may be there established. For be ing the cause of existence to other things, and not deriving that which it is from others, nor its happiness, what addition can be made to it external to itself? Hence its happiness, or the excellency of its condition, is not acci dental to it. For it is itself [all that is suffi cient to itself]. There is not likewise any place for it. For it is not in want of a foun dation, as if it were not able to sustain itself. . . . But other things are established on account of the one, through which also they at the same time subsist, and have the place in which they are arranged. . * . Every thing which is said to be indigent, is indigent of a good condition, and of that which pre serves it. Hence to the one nothing is good, and, therefore, neither is the wish for anything good to it. But it is super-good. And it is not good to itself, but to other things, which are able to participate of it." 1 Adhering to such teachings, Emerson came to ground his doctrine of self-reliance on the reality of the mystic experience in which the One imparts its nature to all things which are 1 Select Works, 487-489. io8 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON resolved into it. Thus he writes in his essay, Self-Reliance : "This is the ultimate fact which we so quickly reach on this, as on every topic, the resolution of all into the ever-blessed One. Self-existence is the attribute of the Supreme Cause, and it constitutes the measure of good by the degree in which it enters into all lower forms. All things real are so by so much virtue as they contain. Commerce, husbandry, hunting, whaling, war, eloquence, personal weight, are somewhat, and engage my respect as examples of its presence and im pure action. I see the same law working in nature for conservation and growth. Power is, in nature, the essential measure of right. Nature suffers nothing to remain in her king doms which cannot help itself. The genesis and maturation of a planet, its poise and orbit, the bended tree recovering itself from the strong wind, the vital resources of every ani mal and vegetable, are demonstrations of the self-sufficing and therefore self-relying soul." * In this same experience Emerson also finds a corrective of the doctrine of indifferency. Into this state of mind he is led by a too literal application to the realm of conduct of the Pythagorean notion of antagonism. Such a 1 Complete Works, II., 70-71. THE OVER-SOUL 109 theory taught that the harmony of the universe resulted from the mutual opposition of antago nistic forces. Blending the notion with the idea of a microcosm, Emerson came to hold that "the true doctrine of omnipresence is that God reappears with all his parts in every moss and cobweb. The value of the universe contrives to throw itself into every point. If the good is there, so is the evil; if the affinity, so the repulsion; if the force, so the limita tion." 1 The logical outcome of such teach ing he sees to be indifferency. "Thus do all things preach the indifferency of circum stances. The man is all. Everything has two sides, a good and an evil. Every advantage has its tax. I learn to be content. But the doctrine of compensation is not the doctrine of indifferency. The thoughtless say, on hear ing these representations — What boots it to do well? there is one event to good and evil; if I gain any good I must pay for it; if I lose any good I gain some other; all actions are indifferent." 2 But Emerson cannot rest thus on the surface of things; he looks beyond the world of cir cumstantial good and evil to the inward world 1 Complete Works, II., 101-102. 2 Ibid., II., 120. i io THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON of the soul and there finds the solution of the question in the presence of the Divine which gives the soul its life. "There is a deeper fact in the soul," he writes, "than compensation, to- wit, its own nature. The soul is not a com pensation, but a life. The soul is. Under all this running sea of circumstance, whose waters ebb and flow with perfect balance, lies the aboriginal abyss of real Being. Essence, or God, is not a relation or a part, but the whole. Being is the vast affirmative, excluding nega tion, self-balanced, and swallowing up all relations, parts and times within itself. Na ture, truth, virtue, are the influx from thence. Vice is the absence or departure of the same." * This transference of the question from an outward world to an inward one recognizes the truth which Plotinus teaches concerning eternity. Eternity is identified with true be ing and "is the same with deity." 2 "Indeed, he who surveys an abundant power collected into one," adds Plotinus, "according to this particular thing which is as it were a subject, he denominates it essence; afterwards, so far as he beholds life in it, he denominates it mo tion; and in the next place, he calls it perma- 1 Ibid., II., 120-121. 2 Select Works, 188. THE OVER-SOUL in nency, so far as it entirely possesses an invariable sameness of subsistence. And he denominates it different and the same, so far as all these are at once one. Thus, therefore, composing these, so as to be at once one life alone, contracting in them difference, and be holding an unceasing sameness of energy, and which never passes from one intelligence or life to another, but always possesses the invari able, and is without interval; beholding all these, he will behold eternity. For he will perceive life abiding in sameness, and always possessing everything present, and not at one time this, and afterwards another thing, but | containing all things at once, and not now some things, and again others. For it is an impartible end; just as in a point where all things subsist at once, and have not yet pro ceeded into a [linear] flux. It likewise abides in the same, i. e., in itself, and does not suffer any change. But it is always in the present, because nothing of it is past, nor again will be in future, but this very thing which it is, it always is." * Opposed to this conception of being Emer son places vice, which he identifies with non- being. "Vice is the absence or departure of *Ibid.f 181-182. U2 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON the same [that is, of being]. Nothing, False hood, may indeed stand as the great Night or shade on which as a background the living universe paints itself forth, but no fact is be gotten by it; it cannot work for it is not. It cannot work any good; it cannot work any harm. It is harm inasmuch as it is worse not to be than to be." 1 Such a conception reflects the views of the Platonists on matter, which is the farthest re moved from true being. "Since matter is neither soul nor intellect," says Plotinus, "nor life, nor form, nor reason, nor bound; for it is infinite; nor power; for what can it effect; but falls off from all these, neither can it rightly receive the appellation of being. But it may deservedly be called non-being. . . . It likewise seems to be full and to be all things, and yet has nothing. But the things which enter into and depart from matter, are imita tions and images of [real] beings, flowing about a formless resemblance; and on account of its formless nature are seen within it. They also appear, indeed, to effect something in it, but effect nothing; for they are vain and debile, and have no resisting power. And since matter, likewise, is void of resistance, 1 Complete Works, II., 121. THE OVER-SOUL 113 they pervade without dividing it, like images in water, or as if some one should send as it were forms into what is called a vacuum.1 . . . So that if someone should say that matter is evil, he will assert what is true, if he says it is impassive to the good, which is the same thing as to say, that it is entirely impas sive." 2 It is in these conceptions of the nature of being and non-being, then, that Emerson finds the solution of the question of compensation. The law is not one of indifferency based on the theory that "there is one event to good and evil; if I gain any good I must pay for it; if I lose any good I gain some other"; the law works in the spiritual world in a positive way. If the criminal adheres to his vice and con tumacy, "inasmuch as he carries the malignity and the lie with him he so far deceases from nature." 3 "Neither can it be said," Emerson adds, "that the gain of rectitude must be bought by any loss. There is no penalty to virtue; no penalty to wisdom; they are proper additions of being. In a virtuous action I properly am; in a virtuous act I add to the 1 Select Works, 142-144. 2 Ibid., 153- 3 Complete Works, II., 121. 114 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON world; I plant into deserts conquered from Chaos and Nothing and see darkness receding on the limits of the horizon." l "There is no tax on the good of virtue, for that is the in coming of God himself, or absolute existence, without any comparative." 2 In such a manner does Emerson use the tenets of Platonism to explain the working of the great law of compensation which had held his attention from early boyhood. He begins his reasoning on the low level of outward cir cumstances which he is led to interpret from the standpoint of two theories embodied in the composite Platonism which he holds — the Pythagorean theory of the world as a harmony of mutually antagonistic elements and the Platonic notion of the microcosm. Each suggestion he develops to the full, but when they lead him to a logical outcome of the in- differency of all moral conduct, he calls a halt and saves himself by introducing an idea of higher power, the doctrine of absolute being and non-being, which by the Platonists were identified with the good and the evil in the inward life. In this ascension the essay, Compensation, ends, with the idea of compen- 1 Ibid., II., 122. •ML THE OVER-SOUL 115 sation mysticized into the doctrine of the pres ence or the absence of the Divine in man as the index of virtue or vice. This result means the final relegation of the Pythagorean element in Emerson's Platonism to a subordinate place. A love of contrasts and of a conception of unity arising out of diverse elements had led Emerson to over develop the Pythagorean notion of the uni verse as a harmony of antagonistic elements. Plato, it is true, uses the categories of the Pythagoreans, but not to the extent of justify ing the prominence that Emerson gave to the notion in his conception of Plato's system; nor does the scheme of Plotinus justify Em erson. It is a clear case of over-statement, the outcome of which speaks much for the corrective influence played by Platonism in Emerson's thinking; it always lies near at hand as a body of thought to guide, to suggest, or to correct his thinking. Such a controlling influence does Platonism exert over Emerson's mind that he finds in its mystical teachings a solution of the questions which the study of the meaning of nature raised. He had gone on the assumption that nature was so intimately allied with the mind of man that "undoubtedly we have no ques- ii6 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON tions to ask which are unanswerable. We must trust the perfection of the creation so far as to believe that whatever curiosity the order of things has awakened in our minds, the order of things can satisfy." * If, then, a mystical experience is the highest experience life can know, the highest truths concerning nature can be known only by virtue of such an experience. Nature, then, must be mysticized. As has been noted already, the method of nature is presented by Emerson as an eternal flux or change due to a superabundance of energy in a metaphysical source. As he views this ceaseless energy he calls it by the name which Plotinus had given to the mystic ex perience. Plotinus describes the participant in such an experience as "being as it were in an ecstacy, or energizing enthusiastically." 2 Emerson applies the term ecstasy to the method of nature. "In short, the spirit and peculiarity of that impression nature makes on us is this, that it does not exist to any one or to any number of particular ends, but to a numberless and endless benefit; that there is in it no private will, no rebel leaf or limb, but the whole is oppressed by one superincumbent 1 Complete Works, I., 3-4. 2 Select Works, 503. THE OVER-SOUL 117 tendency, obeys that redundancy or excess of life which in conscious beings we call ecstasy" 1 When Emerson retired to Nantasket Beach to write The Method of Nature he took with him Plato's Phcedrus, Meno, and Banquet, which he diligently read. He also had with him Proclus, Ocellus Lucanus and certain Pythagorean Fragments, either those of De- mophilus, or those to be found in the Life of Pythagoras by lamblichus.2 It is natural, then, to expect a decided influence in his essay of such reading. Now Ocellus Lucanus, in a short treatise, set forth the eternal nature of the universe as it was understood by the Platonists. "It is credible," he says, "that the universe is with out beginning, and without an end, from its figure, from motion, from time and its essence; and, therefore, it may be concluded that the world is unbegotten and incorrupti ble: for the form of its figure is circular; but a circle is on all sides similar and equal, and is, therefore, without a beginning, and without an end. The motion, also, of the universe is circular, but this motion is stable and without 1 Complete Works, I., 203-204. 2 Ibid., IV., 310. n8 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON transition. Time, likewise, in which motion exists is infinite, for this neither had a begin ning, nor will have an end of its circulation. The essence, too, of the universe is without egression [into any other place], and is im mutable, because it is not naturally adapted to be changed, either from the worse to the better, or from the better to the worse. From all these arguments, therefore, it is obviously credible that the world is unbegotten and in corruptible." 1 Such a conception was easily caught up by Emerson. It taught the eternity of nature whose operations indicated a ceaseless round of energizing. Emerson's adherence to the truth of the correlation of matter and mind made it easy to transfer the idea of ecstasy, which strictly applies to conscious beings, to the method of nature. He thus speaks of nature as "a work of ecstasy, to be represented > by a circular movement, as intention might be : signified by a straight line of definite length." 2 But this application of the doctrine of cor relation leads to a palpable over-statement. Usually, Emerson argues from a law of nature to a law of mind; but in this case he 1 On the Nature of the Universe, S-g. 2 Complete Works, I., 201. THE OVER-SOUL 119 has done the reverse. Ecstasy is attributed to nature and not deduced from her method. It is true that in the opening of his essay he approaches the subject in his usual manner of studying nature for what it reveals of the mind, but in reality it is the idea of ecstasy as a law of the mind that forms the true sub ject of his work. Its closing part thus shows how there is no function or office in man but is rightly discharged by this divine method. True science is ecstatic. In the pursuit of virtue he who aims at progress should aim at an infinite, not a special benefit. The law of ecstasy holds also in love, in genius, and in history. Filled with the idea, then, he strained truth somewhat in boldly teaching ecstasy as the law of nature. Emerson is more successful in identifying man and nature when he describes the mystic experience. A complete union of the soul of man with the Divine means an absolute one ness of man with all things as well. "In that deep force," he writes, "the last fact behind which analysis cannot go, all things find their common origin. For the sense of being which in calm hours rises, we know not how, in the soul, is not diverse from things, from space, from light, from time, from man, but 120 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON one with them, and proceeds obviously from the same source whence their life and being also proceed. We first share the life by which things exist and afterwards see them as appear ances in nature and forget that we have shared their cause." l This is a conception of being which Plotinus had taught him to appreciate. "This is that which is entirely being," writes Plotinus; "and this again is that which in no respect is deficient in existence. But since it is per fectly being, it is not in want of any thing in order that it may be preserved and be, but to other things which appear to be, it is the cause of their apparent existence. ... It is necessary, however, that it should be per fectly being. Hence it is requisite it should accede to existence, possessing all things in itself, and being at once all things, and one all, if by these peculiarities we define being." 2 The mysticism of Plotinus was also effective in providing another solution of the question of the origin of the outward universe. When we ask the questions, Whence is matter? and Whereto? we learn, so Emerson tells us, "that the highest is present to the soul of man; 1 Complete Works, II., 64. 2 Select Works, 137-138. THE OVER-SOUL 121 that the dread universal essence, which is not wisdom, or love, or beauty, or power, but all in one, and each entirely, is that for which all things exist, and that by which they are; that spirit creates; that behind nature, throughout nature, spirit is present; one and not compound it does not act upon us from without, that is, in space and time, but spirit ually, or through ourselves: therefore, that spirit, that is, the Supreme Being, does not build up nature around us, but puts it forth through us, as the life of the tree puts forth new branches and leaves through the pores of the old." 1 In such a statement is recognized the teach ing of Plotinus regarding the creative power of souls. "It is requisite," he holds, "that there should not only be souls, but that their effects also should have a perspicuous subsist ence (since every nature possesses an essential ability of producing something posterior to itself, and of unfolding it into light from its occult subsistence in dormant power), and this as if from a certain indivisible principle and seed, proceeding to a sensible extremity, while that which has a priority of subsistence always abides in its proper seat, but that which 1 Complete Works, L, 63-64. 122 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON is consequent is generated from an ineffable power, such as belongs to superior beings, and is the proper characteristic of their nature." 1 A similar explanation Plotinus gives in his doctrine of the emanation of all things from the One. Of the One he writes: "What shall we say he is? The power of all things, without whose subsistence the universality of things would never have had a being; nor would intellect have been, which is the first and universal life; for that which subsists above life is the cause of life: since energy of life, which is all things, is not the first, but emanates from this principle as its ineffable fountain. . . . Or conceive the life of a mighty tree, propagating itself through the whole tree, the principle at the same time re maining without being divided through the whole, but, as it were, established in the root; this, then, will afford an universal and abun dant life to the tree, but will abide itself, with out multiplication, and subsisting as the principle of multitude." 2 As a result of the doctrine of emanation, Emerson regards nature as a perpetual effect. She is passive to the presence of the Divine 1 Five Books of Plotinus, 275-276. 2 Ibid., 237-238. THE OVER-SOUL 123 power just as man should be; her passiveness corresponds to man's humility. "The aspect of Nature is devout," Emerson holds. "Like the figure of Jesus, she stands with bended head, and hands folded upon the breast. The happiest man is he who learns from nature the lesson of worship.'7 1 Such conceptions reflect the teachings of Plotinus. His system had ended in establish ing the absolute self-sufficiency of the One as well as the absolute nonentity of matter. Between these two extremes was a series of beings who owe all their life to a power over them of which the One is the ultimate source. By submission, then, matter was endowed with quality and so likewise soul. And though the life of the soul seems an upward progress with a union of itself with the One as its end, yet in reality this progress is made by ridding itself of all its characteristic life in order to unite itself with the Divine. Submission, therefore, becomes the one necessary condition on which nature and man can hope to have being: for their life is given to them by this Over-Soul. In the treatment of the Over-Soul we can appreciate the hold which the system of 1 Complete Works, I., 61. 124 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON Plotinus had upon Emerson's way of thought. Toward the end of Nature he reviews his attempts to explain matter and he finds them deficient. The theories of symbolism and correlation of mind and matter did not suffice. They suggested spirit, but they left God out of him. In other words, he finds these ideal istic theories inadequate to explain the mean ing of the universe ; idealism is but "a useful introductory hypothesis, serving to apprize us of the eternal distinction between soul and the world." * It is to mysticism, then, that he turns for the final solution. Mysticism thus becomes the most important element in Emerson's Platonism. In his re view of Plato he notes the absence of this ele ment in Plato's work. Yet he holds that "mysticism finds in Plato all its texts ;" 2 and he agrees with the Platonists in making Plato do honor to the ineffable One, which it is the object of mysticism to realize in the experience of man. But Emerson does not find Plato teaching this doctrine, for he remarks of him, "he never writes in ecstasy, or catches us up into poetic raptures." 3 This mystic 1 Complete Works, L, 63. 2 Ibid., IV., 40. *Ibid., IV., 61. INTELLECT 125 enjoyment Plotinus afforded him. It was natural, then, that he should find Plotinus the great need of his life at one time; for in him he became acquainted with a scheme of thought in which mysticism of the purest in tellectual type was taught. II. INTELLECT. The mysticism of Plotinus is a rational mysticism; it arises as a logical result of a purely rational conception of knowledge. It is an experience which intellect enjoys, intel lect being the principle of soul next in order to the One, or the principle of unity. Thus it comes about that Plotinus and the Platonists have much to say of intellect. And as teach ers of the intellect Emerson esteems the Platonists most highly. In his primary conception of intellect Em erson is one with the Platonists. "How can we speak of the action of the mind under any divisions, as of its knowledge, of its ethics, of its works, and so forth, since it melts will into perception, knowledge into act? Each be comes the other. Itself alone is. Its vision 126 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON is not like the vision of the eye, but is union with the things known." l Such is the teach ing of Plotinus also. Describing intellect, he writes in a sentence, a part of which Emer son appropriates, "It likewise alone is, and is always, but is never future; for when the future arrives, it then also is; nor is it the past." 2 He furthermore holds : "Whatever it possesses, it possesses from itself. But if it perceives intellectually by and from itself, it is itself that which it perceives." 3 Emerson also agrees with the teaching of Platonism in holding that all thought is but a reception rather than a self-directed activity of the mind from within outward. "Our think ing," he holds, "is a pious reception. Our truth of thought is therefore vitiated as much by too violent direction given by our will, as by too great negligence. We do not deter mine what we will think. We only open our senses, clear away as well as we can all ob struction from the fact, and suffer the intellect to see." 4 More explicitly, thought "is the advent of truth into the world, a form of thought now for the first time bursting into 1 Complete Works, II., 323. z Select Works, 263. 8 Ibid., 292. 4 Complete Works, II., 328. INTELLECT 127 the universe, a child of the old eternal soul, a piece of genuine and immeasurable great ness." In the manner in which according to Ploti- nus the One gives birth to Intellect is found the method of reasoning which Emerson uses in describing all thinking as reception. The One is self-sufficient and, therefore, is in need of no creatures for its own satisfaction. And yet it possesses such superabundant energy that it overflows; and this overflow constitutes potential intellect. "For the one" writes Plotinus, "being perfect, in consequence of not seeking after, or possessing, or being in want of anything, it becomes as it were overflow ing, and the super-plenitude of it produces something else. That, however, which is gen erated from it is converted to it, and is filled, and was generated looking to it. But this is intellect." 2 Thus conversion to the One con stitutes the essence of intellect; the state previous to this conversion can be only po tentially intellectual. And this conversion to the One is what Emerson means in his teach ing that all thought is but a pious reception. At the same time that Emerson views think- > d., II., 335- 2 Select Works, 398. ia8 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON ing as a pious reception, he also describes it as an ascending process of mind in search of an absolute cause. This is the conception underlying his essay, Circles. "Our life," he says, "is an apprenticeship to the truth that around every circle another can be drawn ; that there is no end in nature, but every end is / a beginning; that there is always another dawn risen on mid-noon, and under every deep a lower deep opens." 1 It is the same process that Plato and the Platonists call the dialectic, or the ascension of mind from particulars to universals. "It is requisite," observes Simplicius, in the de scription of this process of mind, which Emer son had marked in his copy of Proclus, "that he who ascends to the principle of things should investigate whether it is possible there can be anything better than the supposed principle; and if something more excellent is found, the same inquiry should again be made respecting that, till we arrive at the highest conceptions, than which we have no longer any more venerable. Nor should we stop in our ascent till we find this to be the case. For there is no occasion to fear that our pro gression will be through an unsubstantial 1 Complete Works, II., 301. INTELLECT 129 void, by conceiving something about the first principles which is greater and more tran scendent than their nature. For it is not pos sible for our conceptions to take such a mighty leap as to equal, and much less to pass beyond the dignity of the first principles of things.'7 l Receptivity and the onward progress of the dialectic seem inconsistent ideas. Both are found, however, in Plotinus. The dialectic he inherited from Plato but the idea of re ceptivity is one which he was logically com pelled to accept by reason of his insistence upon the nature of the One as the source of all things and yet as a principle apart from all things and in no need of them. Only by put ting itself in a passive state could a being be neath the One receive its influence. The life of the intellect is thus a progress of the soul ever ascending into new realms but ever divesting itself of all it has received in the realm it has just passed through. These two ideas — that of the dialectic and that of thought as reception — Emerson takes over from Plotinus and makes no attempt to reconcile them. He treats each as it suits his purpose. Emerson agrees with Platonism in teach- 1 Quoted in Proclus, On the Theology of Plato, I., Intro duction, p. 32. 130 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON ing that intellect has power to annul fate. Fate he finds everywhere, "in matter, mind, morals; in race, in retardations of strata, and in thought and character as well." l And by fate he means laws of the world, fate being felt as bound or limitation.2 But he main tains: "Intellect annuls fate. So far as a man thinks, he is free." 3 He explains this triumph of thought over fate more fully. "The revelation of Thought takes man out of servitude into freedom. We rightly say of ourselves, we were born and afterward we were born again, and many times . . . The day of days, the great day of the feast of life, is that in which the inward eye opens to the Unity in things, to the omnipresence of law : — sees that what is must be and ought to be, or is the best ... If truth come to our mind we suddenly expand to its dimen sions, as if we grew to worlds. We are as law-givers ; we speak for Nature : we prophesy and divine." 4 In stating this doctrine Emerson is follow ing the argument of Proclus On Providence 1 Complete Works, VI., 21. 2 Ibid., VI., 4, 21-22. a Ibid.f VI., 23. *Ibid., VI, 25. INTELLECT 131 and Fate. Proclus' conception of fate is one with Emerson's. "If therefore, not only in us, and other animals and plants," observes Proclus, "but in this universe also much prior to bodies, there is one nature of the world, which is corrective and motive of the subsistence of bodies; as it is also in us, (or why do we call all bodies the progeny of na ture?), it is indeed necessary that nature should be the cause of things that are con nected, and that in this what we call Fate should be investigated. And on this account perhaps the daemoniacal Aristotle also is ac customed to call those augmentations or gen erations which are effected beside the accus tomed time, deviations from Fate. And the divine Plato says, 'that the world considered by itself, without the intellectual Gods, is con volved as being corporeal by Fate and innate desire.' The oracles of the gods also accord with these and bear witness to our demonstra tions when they say: 'Look not upon Na ture, for the name of it is fatal.' And thus we have discovered what Fate is, and how it is the nature of this world, and a certain incor poreal essence." 1 Fate thus becomes identi- 1 On the Theology of Plato, II., 450. 132 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON fied with the operations of nature. Or as Emerson puts it, "the book of Nature is the book of fate." 1 It is to be noted that the oracle referred to is used by Emerson. "It is wholesome to man," he observes, "to look not at Fate, but the other way: the practical view is the other. His sound relation to these facts is to use and command, not to cringe to them. 'Look not on Nature for her name is fatal,' said the oracle. The too much contemplation of these limits induces meanness." 2 Proclus also teaches that the way of escape from fate is through the intellectual activity of the soul. "In short, we must say," he writes, "that the rational and intellectual soul in whatever way it may energize, is beyond body and sense; and therefore it is necessary that it should have an essence separable from both these. This, however, though of itself now evident, I will again manifest from hence, that when it energizes according to nature, it is superior to the influence of Fate, but that when it falls into sense, and becomes irrational and corporeal, it follows the natures that are beneath it, and living with them as 1 Complete Works, VI., 15. 2 Ibid., VI., 23. INTELLECT 133 with intoxicated neighbours, is held in subjec tion by a cause that has dominion over things that are different from the rational essence." 1 And the highest form of intellectual action, he tells us, "is obtained by exciting the pro fundity of the soul, which is no longer intel lectual, and adapting it to union with the one!' 2 It is the same mystic experience that Emerson refers to as the day "in which the in ward eye opens to the Unity of things." 3 As an inference from the superior power of of intellect to rise above the limitations of fate Emerson presents a slightly new conception of fate. "Fate then," he concludes, "is a name for facts not yet passed under the fire of thought; for causes which are unpenetrated." 4 It is, however, in accordance with the notion of Proclus who holds that "we denominate that which is evolved through many causes complicated with each other and unknown to us, no otherwise than Fate." 5 Emerson also agrees with the Platonists in the conception of the ascendency of intellect over time. As Proclus states it, "Every in- 1On the Theology of Plato, II., 456. *Ibid., 464. 8 Complete Works, VI., 25. * Ibid., VI., 31. 5 On the Theology of Plato, II., 447. 134 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON tellect has its essence, power and energy in eternity." 1 Emerson shares the same belief when he states: "All our intellectual action, not promises but bestows a feeling of absolute existence. We are taken out of time and breathe a purer air. I know not whence we draw the assurance of prolonged life, of a life which shoots that gulf we call death and takes hold of what is real and abiding, by so many claims as from our intellectual history." 2 On this power of intellect Emerson bases his belief in immortality. "This is the way we rise," he tells us. "Within every man's thought is a higher thought — within the char acter he exhibits to-day a higher character. The youth puts off the illusions of the child, the man puts off the ignorance and the tumul tuous passions of youth; proceeding thence puts off the egotism of manhood, and be comes at last a public and universal soul. He is rising to greater heights, but also rising to realities; the outer relations and circum stances dying out, he entering deeper into God, God into him, until the last garment of egotism falls, and he is with God— shares the -12. 2 Complete Works, VIII., 340. INTELLECT 135 will and the immensity of the First Cause." 1 It is a way of reasoning that Plotinus had taught him. "Now, however, men perceiv ing that the soul of the greater part of the human race is defiled with vice, they do not reason about it either as a divine or an im mortal thing. But it is necessary, in consid ering the nature of everything, to direct our attention to the purity of it; since whatever is added, is always an impediment to the knowl edge of that to which it is added. Consider the soul, therefore, by taking away [that which is extraneous] ; or rather, let him who takes this away survey himself, and he will believe himself to be immortal, when he be holds himself in the intelligible world, and situated in a pure abode. For he will per ceive intellect seeing not anything sensible, nor any of these mortal objects, but by an eternal power contemplating that which is eternal ; everything in the intelligible world, and itself also being then luminous, in conse quence of being enlightened by the truth pro ceeding from the good, which illuminates all intelligibles with reality. By such a soul as this, therefore, it may be properly said, id., VIII., 348-349. 136 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON Farewell, a God immortal now am I, having ascended to divinity, and earnestly striving to become similar to him." 1 A less mystic explanation of the manner in which intellectual activity makes for immor tality is found in the feeling of absoluteness attendent upon the vision of truth. "Salt," Emerson explains, "is a good preserver; cold is: but a truth cures the taint of mortality bet ter, and 'preserves from harm until another period.' A sort of absoluteness attends all perception of truth — no smell of age, no hint of corruption. It is self-sufficing, sound, en tire." 2 As the quotation Emerson uses shows, the idea is Plato's. In his Phcedrus Plato ex plains how the human soul, which is immor tal, lived in the eternal world before it ap peared on earth. Its main care in that world was to behold truth. "And this is the rea son," Plato adds, "for the great anxiety to be hold the field of truth, where it is; the proper pasture for the best part of the soul happens to be in the meadow there, and it is the na ture of the wing by which the soul is borne aloft, to be nourished by it; and this is a 1 Select Works, 243. 2 Complete Works, VIIL, 340. INTELLECT 137 law of Adrastia, that whatever soul, in ac companying a deity, has beheld any of the true essences, it shall be free from harm until the next revolution, and if it can always ac complish this, it shall be always free from harm." 1 Eternity, then, in which intellect has its be ing, takes the place in Emerson's thought of immortality; it involves, as he says, "not dura tion but a state of abandonment to the High est, and so the sharing of His perfection." 2 "Is immortality," he asks, "only an intellec tual quality, or, shall I say, only an energy, there being no passive? He has it, and he alone, who gives life to all names, persons, things where he comes. No religion, not the wildest mythology dies for him; no art is lost. He vivifies what he touches. Future state is an illusion for the ever-present state. It is not length of life, but depth of life. It is not duration, but a taking of the soul out of time, as all high action of the mind does: when we are living in the sentiments we ask no questions about time. The spiritual world takes place — that which is always the same." 3 iBohn translation, I., 324. 2 Complete Works, VIIL, 349. s Ibid., 347- 138 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON This conception is identical with the teach ing of Platonism. "According to the oracle," says Proclus, "eternity is the cause of never- failing life, of unwearied power, and unslug- gish energy. . . . Eternity is the father and supplier of infinite life; since eternity is also the cause of all immortality — and perpe tuity. And Plotinus, exhibiting, in a most divinely inspired manner, the peculiarity of eternity, according to the theology of Plato defines it to be infinite life, at once unfolding into light the whole of itself, and its own be ing . . . For eternity is infinite power abiding in one, and proceeding stably." 1 In his conception of intellect, then, Emer son agrees with the teachings of Platonism in regarding the nature of the intellect's vision as an actual union with the thing seen, in hold ing that thinking is receptivity and at the same time an onward progress of the mind, and in maintaining the triumph of intellect over fate and time. 1 On the Theology of Plato, I., 190-191. THE WORLD-SOUL 139 in. THE WORLD-SOUL. Thus far Emerson has spoken of soul as present chiefly in the consciousness of men; but he holds with the Platonists that there is a soul at work in the universe outside of man as well as in his inward life. This is with him "the sublime creed that the world is not the product of manifold power, but of one will, of one mind; and that one mind is every where active, in each ray of the star, in each wavelet of the pool; and whatever opposes that will is everywhere balked and baffled, be cause things are made so, and not otherwise." 1 This belief corresponds to the tenet of Uni versal Soul taught by Platonism. Below the One and Intellect is the Anima Mundi, the Universal Soul, which is the intermediating principle between the world of pure intelli gence and the world of matter. "Every soul," writes Plotinus, "ought to consider in the first place, that soul produced all animals, and in spired them with life: viz., those animals which the earth and sea nourish, those which live in the air, and the divine stars contained 1 Complete Works, I., 123-124. 140 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON in the heavens. Soul also made the sun ; soul made and adorned this mighty heaven. Soul, too, circumvolves it in an orderly course, be ing of a nature different from the things which it adorns, which it moves, and causes to live, and is necessarily more honourable than these. . . . What the mode is, however, by which life is supplied to the universe, and to each of its parts, may be considered to be as follows : . . . Let a quiet soul behold that other mighty soul, externally as it were, on all sides flowing and infused into, pene trating and illuminating the quiescent mass. For just as the rays of the sun darting on a dark cloud cause it to become splendid, and golden to the view, thus also, soul entering into the body of heaven gave it life, gave it im mortality, and excited it from its torpid state. But heaven being moved with a perpetual mo tion, through the guidance of a wise soul, became a blessed animal. It also acquired dignity through soul becoming its inhabitant, since, prior to soul it was a dead body, viz., earth and water, or rather the darkness of mat ter and non-entity; and as some one says, 'that which the Gods abhor.' " l Emerson uses the conception of the Anima 1 Select Works, 256-258. THE WORLD-SOUL 141 Mundi in his poem, The World-Soul. As a refuge, from the vice of men in the centers of wealth and trade he turns to glances of a spirit which haunts him, in the broad aspects of nature, in human beings, in strains of music. Its secret has never been fully solved but its operations in the world are constant and relentless. "But soul," observes Plotinus, speaking of the soul of the world, "by the power of essence has dominion over bodies in such a way, that they are generated and sub sist, just as she leads them, since they are un able from the first to oppose her will." 1 Or as Emerson puts it: "For Destiny never swerves Nor yields to men the helm; He shoots his thoughts, by hidden nerves, Throughout the solid realm. The patient Daemon sits, With roses and a shroud; He has his way, and deals his gifts — But ours is not allowed." 2 In this power Emerson finds the hope of the world, which will be fulfilled in a fairer 345. 2 Complete Works, IX., 18. 142 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON world which the world-soul will create out of this one. A finer poetic result of Emerson's musings on the world-soul is to be found in his little lyric, Music, in which he works out a sugges tion he found in a note appended by Taylor to a passage in Proclus. Commenting on the mutual sympathy shared by all things in the universe, Taylor remarks that he who holds to such a belief "will survey the universe as one great animal, all whose parts are in union and consent with each other; so that nothing is foreign and detached; nothing, strictly speak ing, void of sympathy and life. For though parts of the world, when considered as sep arated from the whole, are destitute of pecul iar life ; yet they possess some degree of ani mation, however inconsiderable, when viewed with relation to the universe. Life indeed may be compared to a perpetual and univer sal sound; and the soul of the world resem bles a lyre, or some other musical instru ment, from which we may suppose this sound to be emitted. But from the unbounded dif fusion as it were of the mundane soul, every thing participates of this harmonical sound, in greater or less perfection, according to the dignity of its nature. So that while life THE WORLD-SOUL 143 everywhere resounds, the most abject of be ings may be said to retain a faint echo of the melody produced by the mundane lyre." 1 In the last sentence of this quotation is the motif of Emerson's poem, Music. "Let me go where'er I will, I hear a sky-born music still : It sounds from all things old, It sounds from all things young, From all that's fair, from all that's foul, Peals out a cheerful song. 'It is not only in the rose, It is not only in the bird, Not only where the rainbow glows, Nor in the song of woman heard, But in the darkest, meanest things There alway, alway something sings. "'Tis not in the high stars alone, Nor in the cup of budding flowers, Nor in the redbreast's mellow tone, Nor in the bow that smiles in showers, But in the mud and scum of things There alway, alway something sings." And thus it appears that Emerson follows the Theology of Plato, II., 395, note i. H4 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON the Platonists in their account of the spiritual principles of the universe. His doctrines of the Over-soul, of Intellect, of a World-Soul are in general agreement with the three prin ciples of the Platonists. But he is not careful to distinguish them scientifically as the Plato nists do ; they all go to inform his conception of Soul. Soul he thus finds everywhere in the highest and lowest of created things ; but his main purpose was to assert its presence, the presence of the Divine, in man, who comes to experience it in a mystical resolution of his own life into that of the Divine. This is the center of Emerson's thought, as it was of Plo- tinus', and it shows itself in his repeated em phasis upon the need of soul in life. So ab sorbing is this power of soul that it includes not only the life of man but the very life of nature. CHAPTER IV LOVE AND BEAUTY A DISCUSSION of love and beauty fig ures somewhat conspicuously in Emer son's work. In his examination into the meaning of nature he finds beauty serving a noble want of man. To this subject he de votes a separate essay in his Conduct of Life and he gives a poetical rendering of the theme in the Ode to Beauty. Likewise in his treat ment of love, a separate essay deals with the question and his poem Initial, Dcemonic and Celestial Love presents the subject in a poeti cal trilogy. Reference to such topics is fre quent in his work; for as an admirer of Plato- nism he came to feel the inspiration which its philosophy of love and beauty stirs within the mind of all its true students. Plenty of material in his Platonic sources was at hand. Plato had given impetus to the discussion in his Banquet and Phcedrus. His quickening influence is felt in Plutarch, who leaves a dialogue on love, and in Plotinus 146 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON whose discussions on beauty, especially, are of first importance in the history of aesthetics. In Taylor's translation of a portion of his En- neads, An Essay on the Beautiful (1792), Emerson had an available source. In the translation of the Select Works of Plotinus he also found a valuable extract On Intelligible Beauty, which he carefully indexed and thor oughly digested. Proclus in his On the The ology of Plato provided him with an ex position which Emerson's index shows was one of his "lustres." In his Commentaries on the Timceus of Plato the same author left other patches of theorizing on beauty. Emerson availed himself of all these sources and in his writings on love and beauty con forms rather strictly to the method of the Platonists. His Initial, Dcemonic and Celestial Love, as its title indicates, is a recognition of a divi sion of the subject which Plato had made in his Banquet. There in the speech of one of the characters, Pausanias, he laid down the distinction between a celestial love and a vulgar love which persisted throughout the entire course of Neo-Platonic speculation.1 Through the mouth of another speaker, Soc- 1 Bohn translation, III., 491. rut LOVE AND BEAUTY 147 rates, who hands down the idea of a certain prophetess, Diotima, Plato also explains that love is "a great daemon . . . and being in the middle space between gods and men it fills up the whole." * Emerson's Initial, Daemonic and Celestial Love thus recognizes the distinction which Plato had made. In developing the subject the influence of Plato- nism makes itself felt especially in the second and third parts — Daemonic and Celestial Love. In setting forth his conception of daemonic love Emerson avails himself of what the ancients had said about daemons. Plato's ref erence to these had started a discussion among the Platonists, which in Plutarch, Plotinus, lamblichus, and Proclus was prolific of much speculation. The subject evidently attracted Emerson who fortunately has left an ab stract of his views as gathered from his sources. "The ancients believed," he writes, "that a genius or demon took possession at birth of each mortal, to guide him ; that these genii were sometimes seen as a flame of fire partly immersed in the bodies which they gov erned; on an evil man, resting on his head; in a good man, mixed with his substance. They 148 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON thought the same genius, at the death of its ward, entered a new born child, and they pretended to guess the pilot by the sailing of the ship." 1 This is an abstract from several sources. In lamblichus' Mysteries of the Egyptians, Chaldeans, and Assyrians, Emerson found in a foot note by Taylor the remark: " Accord ing to the Egyptians every one received his proper daemon at the hour of his birth." 2 And in the text of the same work he had noted that "there is one daemon who is the guardian and governor of everything that is in us." 3 In Plutarch's dialogue A Discourse Concern ing Socrates' s Dcemon, Emerson found an ac count of the connection between men and daemons on which he bases the second part of his statement. "Every soul doth not mix her self after one sort," Plutarch observes, "for some plunge themselves into the body, and so in this life their whole frame is corrupted by appetite and passion; others are mixed as to some part, but the purer part still remains without the body — it is not drawn down into it, but it swims above, and touches the ex- 1 Complete Works, VI., 287. 2 p. 320, note, s p. 322. LOVE AND BEAUTY 149 tremest part of the man's head; it is like a cord to hold up and direct the subsiding part of the soul, as long as it proves obedient and is not overcome by the appetites of the flesh. That part that is plunged into the body is called the soul, but the uncorrupted part is called the mind, and the vulgar think it is within them as likewise they imagine the image reflected from a glass to be in that. But the more intelligent, who know it to be without, call it a Daemon." 1 It is to be noted, however, that Emerson does not follow Plutarch's distinction be tween the daemon in the good and in the evil man. In Plutarch the daemon re mains above the good man; in Emerson the daemon in the good man is mixed throughout his substance and in the bad man rests upon his head. This difference may be due to an inaccurate interpretation of Plutarch; or, it may be, that in his account Emerson has blended the notion which Proclus gives of the daemon of Socrates, who "according to the energy of his daemon, received the light pro ceeding from thence, neither in his dianoetic part alone, nor in his doxastic powers, but also in his spirit, the illumination of the daemon 1 Morals, II., 410. i,5o THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON suddenly diffusing itself through the whole of his life, and now moving sense itself." 1 The final portion of Emerson's statement refers to a passage in Plutarch's dialogue which Emerson himself extracts in his essay on Plutarch. "Early this morning, asking Epaminondas about the manner of Lysis's burial, I found that Lysis had taught him as far as the incommunicable mysteries of our sect; and that the same Daemon that waited on Lysis, presided over him, if I can guess at the pilot from the sailing of the ship." 2 These beliefs concerning the daemon Emer son works into his poem, Dcemonic Lovt: "Close, close to men, Like undulating layer of air, High above their heads, The potent plain of Daemons spreads. Stands to each human soul its own, For watch and ward and furtherance, In the snares of Nature's dance; And the lustre and the grace To fascinate each youthful heart, Beaming from its counterpart, Translucent through the mortal covers, Is the Daemon's form and face. 1 Quoted in The Works of Plato, translated by Thomas Taylor, I., 22-23. 2 Morals, II., 399. LOVE AND BEAUTY 151 To and fro the Genius hies — A gleam which plays and hovers Over the maiden's head, And dips sometimes as low as to her eyes." 1 In this passage there is a recognition of the existence of a guardian spirit over each hu man soul and of the manner of its appearance as Plutarch had given it in his picturesque ex planation of the relation between the daemon and its ward, the soul. In developing the idea of a multitude of daemons above us Emer son was working in accordance with a note on the benevolent daemons given by Taylor in his Plato: "They stand," he writes of the daemons, "as it were over our heads, discourse with each other, and in the mean time specu late our affairs, disapprove our evil deeds, and commend such as are good." 2 The conception of daemonic love set forth in Emerson is two fold. Daemonic love is first presented as a love of beauty in its noble purity. This beauty snaps all the ties the soul has recognized and leads the soul to follow in its quest. The daemons lend this alluring beauty unto men. But there is another race of daemons who skirt man's path with strength 1 Complete Works, IX., no. 2 III., 343, note I. 152 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON and terror.1 That is, there are evil daemons as well as good and an evil daemonic love along with a noble kind. The evil kind of daemonic love is character istic of those geniuses who exult in their own intellectual prowess and insult the multitude; it is a love springing out of the pride of intel lect. Thus the inspiring daemons of this evil love are described: "The Daemons are self-seeking Their fierce and limitary will Draws men to their likeness still." 2 This idea is in keeping with what Synesius writes of evil daemons : "These daemons, who are the progeny of matter wish to make souls their own, and the manner in which they at tack them is as follows : It is not possible in the earth that there should be someone who has not a portion of the irrational soul . . . Evil daemons through this, as through that which is allied to them, invade and betray the animal. . . , Thus daemons inflame de sire, thus they inflame anger, and all such evils as are the sisters of these; associating with souls through the parts that are adapted to 1 Complete Works, IX., HI. LOVE AND BEAUTY 153 themselves, which naturally perceive the pres ence of the daemons, and are excited and cor roborated by them, rising against intellect, till they either vanquish the whole soul, or de spair of its caption." 1 Of the fate of these destructive daemons Emerson writes : "Therefore comes an hour from Jove Which his ruthless will defies, And the dogs of Fate unties." 2 This means the destruction of the daemon and his work. The suggestion probably came from Cud- worth, who speaks of "those Empedoclean demons lapsed from heaven, and pursued with divine vengeance," 3 which Plutarch had re ferred to.4 These daemons had been driven out of heaven by the offended gods and forced to wander about in restless torment. The parallel, at any rate, is quite in keeping with Emerson's way of using the fragments of mythology he found in Cudworth. In his treatment of celestial love also the tenets of Platonism are boldly expressed. In 1 On Providence, in Select Works of Plotinus, 535. 2 Complete Works, IX., 113. 3 The True Intellectual System of the Universe, I., 47. 4 Plutarch, Morals, V., 420-421. 154 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON keeping with the scheme of an ascending scale of love which Platonism had developed, Emerson places celestial love at the summit. "Higher far into the pure realm, Over sun and star, Over the flickering Daemon film, Thou must mount for love; Into vision where all form Into one only form dissolves; In a region where the wheel On which all beings ride Visibly revolves; Where the starred, eternal worm Girds the world with bound and term; Where unlike things are like; Where good and ill, And joy and moan, Melt into one. "There Past, Present, Future, shoot Triple blossoms from one root; Substances at base divided, In their summits are united ; There the holy essence rolls, One through separated souls; And the sunny JEon sleeps Folding Nature in its deeps, And every fair and every good, Known in part, or known impure, To men below, LOVE AND BEAUTY 155 In their archetypes endure, The race of gods, Or those we erring own, Are shadows flitting up and down In the still abodes. The circles of that sea are laws Which publish and which hide the cause." 1 At the basis of this conception lies the idea of the absolute unity of things. The love of this is a celestial love. "For, since the soul is different from God," says Plotinus in one of his accounts of the union of the soul with the One — the god he speaks of, "but is derived from him, she necessarily loves him, and when she is there she has a celestial love; but the love which she here possesses is common and vulgar. For in the intelligible world the celestial Venus reigns, but here the popular Venus, who is as it were meretricious." 2 Thus in explaining the nature of this love Emerson accepts the Plotinian or Neo-Pla- tonic scheme rather than the Platonic, which ended in a vision of absolute beauty rather than of an absolute One. In Emerson love ends in a contemplation of the absolute oneness of all form, conditions, substances, and souls. Of 1 Complete Works, IX., 115-116. 2 Select Works, 497. 156 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON this principle Plotinus writes: "But that is formless, and is even without intelligible form. For the nature of the one being gen erative of all things, is not any one of them. Neither therefore, is it a certain thing, nor a quality, nor a quantity, nor intellect, nor soul, nor that which is moved, nor again that which stands still. Nor is it in place, or in time; but is by itself uniform, or rather without form, being prior to all form, to motion and to permanency." * The couplet explaining how Past, Present, and Future shoot from one root is a reminis cence of the conception of the intelligible world which possesses all things in eternity. For intellect, which there reigns, as Plotinus says, "alone is, and is always, but is never fu ture; for when the future arrives, it then also is; nor is it the past" 2 One with Plotinus is the idea of the exist ence of all things in their archetypes in the world of pure intellect. He holds that all be ings exist primarily in intellect. "Hence," he adds, "it is necessary that these things should be prior to the world, not as impres sions from other things, but as archetypes, and 1 Select Works, 478. 2 Ibid., 263. LOVE AND BEAUTY 157 primary natures, and the essence of the intel lect." 1 Inasmuch as in intellect all things are together without respect to time and place, they are conceived by Plotinus to be in eter nity2 — an idea which Emerson alludes to in his lines on JEon. lEon is the English name for a«oi/ (eternity). Into Emerson's account the imagery of Plato's Phcedrus also enters. In his narrative of the life of souls in the intelligible world Plato tells how all that are able revolve about pure ideas which they behold and whose life they drink in. "For those that are called im mortal," he writes, "when they reach the sum mit, proceeding outside, stand on the back of heaven, and while they are stationed here, its revolution carries them round, and they be hold the external regions of heaven." 3 Al luding to this Emerson thus directs the lover to "a region where the wheel On which all beings ride Visibly revolves." 4 The nature of poetry permitted Emerson to 1 /&»« m h|s discussion of the uses of nature. According to Plutarch, "Pythagoras was the first philosopher that gave the name of ^oV/to? to the world from the order and beauty of it; for so the word signifies." * Following such a definition Emerson finds in the love of natural objects one of the uses, though not the final use, in which nature serves man. Thus he opens the discussion of beauty in Nature with the state ment — "The ancient Greeks called the world /coVos, beauty. Such is the constitution of all things, or such the plastic power of the human eye, that the primary forms as the sky, the mountain, the tree, the animal, give us a delight in and for themselves; a pleasure aris ing from outline, color, motion and group- ing."2 Emerson's reading in the Platonists, then, was a great stimulus to his appreciation of beauty. Their conception of a gradation of beauty provided him with a critical scheme to value beauty in its primary manifestation and up through the moral and intellectual worlds into the realm of pure imagination. The teaching of Proclus of the cosmical 1 Morals, III., 132. 2 Complete Works, I., 15. LOVE AND BEAUTY 185 nature of beauty, by which the individual is related to the universal scheme of things, ap pealed most strongly to Emerson. It satisfied a mind that loved to lose itself in the thought of universals and it enabled him to appreciate the fugitive character of beauty arising out of its cosmical quality. Beauty is thus not identified with form, symmetry, or color, but is a liveliness quite distinct from these. In catching this fascinating quality of beauty Emerson gets nearer to the spirit of Platonism than when he develops his ideal of love. CHAPTER V ART THE question of art is closely associated in Emerson with the larger question of nature. In his introduction to Nature he includes the term art under his main topic. "Nature, in the common sense," so his defini tion runs, "refers to essences unchanged by man; space, the air, the river, the leaf. Art is applied to the mixture of his will with the same things, as in a house, a canal, a statue, a picture. But his operations taken together are so insignificant, a little chipping, baking, patching and washing, that in an impression so grand as that of the world on the human mind, they do not vary the result." * Later in life, he attended to this matter of art with a fullness of treatment in keeping with the im portance of the subject; but throughout his art criticism there is a close connection be tween his theories of nature and those of art. Art, so Emerson conceives its general im- 1 Complete Works, L, 5. 1 86 ART 187 port, is one way in which the Universal Mind reveals itself in the activities of the individual. "I hasten to state," his account runs, "the principle which prescribes, through different means, its firm law to the useful and the beautiful arts. The law is this. The uni versal soul is the alone creator of the useful and the beautiful; therefore, to make any thing useful or beautiful, the individual must be submitted to the universal mind." 1 In both the useful and the fine arts, nature is a representative of the universal mind. "In the first place," he proceeds, "let us consider this in reference to the useful arts. Here the omnipotent agent is Nature; all human acts are satellites to her orb. Nature is the rep resentative of the universal mind, and the law becomes this — that Art must be a complement to Nature, strictly subsidiary." 2 In apply ing the idea to the fine arts he adds, "Nature paints the best part of the picture, carves the best part of the statue, builds the best part of the house, and speaks the best part of the oration." 3 As regards the spiritual side of a work of art, "the parts must be subordinate 1 Ibid., VII., 40. 2 Ibid. ., 47. 188 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON to Ideal Nature, and everything individual abstracted, so that it shall be the production of the universal soul." 1 He thus concludes: "There is but one Reason. The mind that made the world is not one mind, but the mind. And every work of art is a more or less pure manifestation of the same." 2 The doctrine of Universal Mind is writ large on such a theory: and that doctrine Em erson had appropriated from Platonism. The subserviency of nature to this mind, how ever, and the part that it and the universal mind play in human art arose out of a sug gestion which Emerson found in Cudworth's essay on plastic nature which he indexed under "Art" in his own copy of The True Intellectual System of the Universe. This plastic nature, Cudworth explains, is "to be conceived as art acting not from without and at a distance, but immediately upon the thing itself which is formed by it." 3 But this plastic nature in its operations is subordinate to the divine mind. Accordingly he states: "Nature is not the Deity itself, but a thing very remote from it, and far below it, so 1 Ibid., 48. 2 Ibid., 50-51. 8 The True Intellectual System of the Universe, I., 235. ART 189 neither is it the divine art, as it is in itself pure and abstract, but concrete and embodied only; for the divine art considered in itself is nothing but knowledge, understanding, or wisdom in the mind of God." 1 "Nature is not master of that consummate art and wis dom, according to which it acts, but only a servant to it, and a drudging executioner of the dictates of it." 2 Quoting Plotinus, from whom the theory is drawn, he says, "That which is called nature is the offspring of a higher soul, which hath a more powerful life in it." 3 Now by substituting his own name for God, namely, Universal Mind, Emerson was able to use Cudworth's account as the basis of his essay, Art. Further evidence of his dependence upon Cudworth is to be found in his preliminary definition of art. "Relatively to themselves," he says, "the bee, the bird, the beaver, have no art; for what they do they do instinctively; but relatively to the Supreme Being, they have. And the same is true of all uncon scious action: relatively to the doer, it is in stinct; relatively to the First Cause, it is Art. id., I, 237-238. 2 Ibid., I., 239. *Ibid., I., 256. 190 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON In this sense, recognizing the Spirit which in forms Nature, Plato rightly said, 'Those things, which are said to be done by Nature are indeed done by Divine Art.' Art, uni versally, is the spirit creative. It was defined by Aristotle, 'The reason of the thing, with out the matter.' " 1 In Cudworth's account both these quota tions are found and in Emerson's copy both are marked. "Wherefore when art is said to imitate nature," writes Cudworth, "the mean ing thereof is, that imperfect human art imi tates that perfect art of nature, which is really no other than the divine art itself; as before Aristotle, Plato had declared in his Sophist, in these words: *. . . Those things which are said to be done by Nature, are indeed done by divine art.' " 2 "Art is defined by Aristotle to be '. . . the rea son of the thing without matter.' " 3 It is also to be recalled that the motto from Plo- tinus prefixed to the first edition of Nature came from this portion of Cudworth where plastic nature is discussed. So imbued is Emerson with the doctrine of 1 Complete Works, VII., 39. 2 The True Intellectual System of the Universe, L, 237. 3 Ibid., L, 238. ART 191 Universal Mind as the creator in all art that he uses it to explain certain phenomena in aesthetics. The pleasure aroused by a work of art seems to arise from our recognizing in it the mind that formed nature again in active operation.1 The same principle also explains the moral grandeur of works of art; they come from absolute mind whose nature is goodness as well as truth.2 The analogies ex isting in all arts likewise find an explanation in the reappearance of one mind working to many temporal ends in many materials.3 The necessity, too, reigning in the world of art is one of the possible forms in the Divine mind discovered and executed by the artist.4 It has already been pointed out how the doctrine of Universal Mind changes into that of the Over-Soul. Both mean the same thing in Emerson. In the Over-Soul he lays em phasis upon the relation of the divine power to the human soul ; the former stands over the latter and guides its activities, just as in the scheme of the Platonists the One is above In tellect and Intellect above Soul, each princi- 1 Complete Works, VII., 51. 2 Ibid. *Ibid., 52. 54. Of THE UNIVERSITY Of 192 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON pie drawing its life from that immediately above it in power. By applying this concep tion to the relation of the divine mind to the artist Emerson explains the manner of crea tion in art: "Know'st thou what wove yon wood-bird's nest Of leaves, and feathers from her breast? Or how the fish outbuilt her shell, Painting with morn each annual cell? Or how the sacred pine-tree adds To her old leaves new myriads? Such and so grew these holy piles Whilst love and terror laid the tiles. Earth proudly wears the Parthenon As the best gem upon her zone, And Morning opes with haste her lids To gaze upon the Pyramids; O'er England's abbeys bends the sky, As on its friends, with kindred eye. These temples grew as grows the grass; Art might obey, but not surpass. The passive Master lent his hand To the vast soul that o'er him planned ; And the same power that reared the shrine Bestrode the tribes that knelt within." 1 * Ibid., IX., 7-& ART 193 Among the arts poetry receives the fullest share of Emerson's attention. In the ideal poet he found the complete man whose ad vent he was ever expecting; in him he looked to find the embodiment under the form of beauty of all that he had come to learn con cerning nature and the soul : in fact the poet and the philosopher were to be one. At first sight this fusion of poetry and phi losophy seems to preclude the influence of Platonism as an important factor in such a result. Plato had banished the poets from his commonwealth and had analyzed their art as an imitation of an imitation and not an imitation of reality. He had thus come to place the poet just a little above a mechanic or farmer. But Plotinus had corrected the error. "If one condemns the arts," he says, "because they create by way of imitation of nature, first we must observe that natural things themselves are an imitation of some thing further [viz., of underlying reasons or ideas], and next we must bear in mind that the arts do not simply imitate the visible, but go back to the reasons from which nature comes; and, further, that they create much out of themselves, and add to that which is 194 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON defective, as being themselves in possession of beauty; since Pheidias did not create his Zeus after any perceived pattern, but made him such as he would be if Zeus deigned to appear to mortal eyes." * Through such reasoning Plotinus brought Platonism back to a fuller realization of the plastic character of its own thought. Plato had appealed to this Greek way of looking at things of the spirit in his account of crea tion; in his Timceus the Creator sets about his work as an artist and fashions the world after an eternal pattern of ideal or intellectual beauty; hence the dependence of this world of sense as an image on the world of true in telligible substance. But he had never ap plied the idea to art. Plotinus, however, did. He turned the tide of imitation into a re sourceful stream of pure creation. Art, then, as a creative idea in the soul of the artist had a beauty surpassing that of the works pro ceeding from it; and just as the Creator in the Timceus was superior to his work, or the universe, so the human artist rises above his work and lives in an essentially ideal world of his own. 1 Quoted in Bernard Bosanquet, A History of ^Esthetic, 113-114- ART 195 In Emerson this conception of art is found in snatches of aesthetic theory. "The beauty of nature re-forms itself in the mind, and not for barren contemplation, but for the new cre ation." 1 "The creation of beauty is Art." 2 "Thus is Art a nature passed through the alem bic of man. Thus in art does Nature work through the will of a man filled with the beauty of her first works." 3 "The soul cre ated the arts wherever they have flourished. It was in his own mind that the artist sought his model." 4 York Minster and St. Peter's are imitations, "faint copies of an invisible archtype." 5 In such statements art is con ceived as a creative power in the artist, and not a mere imitation lacking reality. But it was Proclus that showed Emerson how the breach between poetry and philoso phy opened by Plato's criticism could be closed. Although Plotinus had justified the artist as a creative agent, he had not attempted to identify him with the philosopher. But this Proclus did in an account of poetry which contains, in the words of Thomas Taylor, who 1 Complete Works, I., 23. 2 Ibid. 3 Ibid., 24. *Ibid., II., S2. rf., I., 68. 196 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON includes the passage in his notes to Plato's Republic, "a most accurate and scientific di vision of poetry, and perfectly reconciles the prince of philosophers with the first of poets." * This reconciliation is brought about by summarily paralleling the activities of the soul with the functions of the various kinds of poetry. "There are three lives in the soul," says Proclus, "of which the best and most perfect is that according to which it is conjoined with the Gods, and lives a life most allied, and through the highest similitude united to them ; no longer subsisting from itself, but from them, running under its own intellect, exciting the ineffable impressions of the one which it contains, and connecting like with like, its own light with that of the Gods, and that which is most uniform in its own essence and life, with the one which is above all essence and life. That which is second to this in dignity and power, has a middle arrangement in the mid dle of the soul, according to which indeed it is converted to itself, descending from a di vinely inspired life; and placing intellect and science as the principles of its energy, it 1 The Works of Plato, translated by Thomas Taylor, I., 438, note. ART 197 evolves the multitude of its reasons, surveys the all-various mutations of forms, collects into sameness intellect, and that which is the object of intellect, and expresses in images an intellectual and intelligible essence. The third life of the soul is that which accords with its inferior powers, and energizes to gether with them, employing phantasies and irrational senses, and being entirely filled with things of a subordinate nature. "As there are therefore these three forms of life in souls, the poetical division also super- nally proceeds together with the multiform lives of the soul, and is diversified into first, middle, and last genera of energy. For, of poetry also, one kind has the highest subsist ence, is full of divine goods, and establishes the soul in the causes themselves of things, ac cording to a certain ineffable union, leading that which is filled, into sameness with its re plenishing source; the former immaterially subjecting itself to illumination, but the latter being excited to a communication of light; thus according to the Oracle, 'perfecting works, by mingling the rivers of incorruptible fire.' It also produces one divine bond and a unifying mixture of that which is partici pated and the participant, establishing the 198 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON whole of that which is subordinate in that which is more excellent, and preparing that which is more divine alone to energize, the in ferior nature being withdrawn, and conceal ing its own idiom in that which is superior. This then, in short, is a mania better than tem perance, and is distinguished by a divine char acteristic. And as every different kind of poetry subsists according to a different hyparxis, or summit of divine essence, so this fills the soul energizing from divine inspira tion, with symmetry; and hence it adorns its last energies with measures and rhythms. As therefore we say that prophetic fury subsists according to truth, and the amatory accord ing to beauty, in the like manner, we say, that the poetic mania is defined according to divine symmetry. "The second kind of poetry which is subor dinate to the first and divinely inspired species, and which has a middle subsistence in the soul, is allotted its essence according to a scientific and intellectual habit. Hence it knows the essence of things and loves to con template beautiful works and reasonings, and leads forth everything into a measured and rhythmical interpretation. For you will find many progeny of good poets to be of this kind, ART 199 emulous of those that are truly wise, full of admonition, the best counsels, and intellectual symmetry. It likewise extends the commu nication of prudence and every other virtue to those of a naturally good disposition, and af fords a reminiscence of the periods of the soul, of its eternal reasons, and various powers. "The third species of poetry subsequent to these, is mingled with opinions and phan tasies, receives its completion through imita tion, and is said to be, and is nothing else than imitative poetry. At one time, it alone uses assimilation, and at another time defends ap parent and not real assimilation. It consid erably raises very moderate passions, aston ishes the hearers; together with appropriate appellations and wrords, mutations of har monies and varieties of rhythms, changes the dispositions of souls; and indicates the nature of things not such as they are, but such as they appear to the many; being a certain adum bration, and not an accurate knowledge of things. It also establishes as its end the de light of the hearers; and particularly looks to the passive part of the soul, which is naturally adapted to rejoice and be affected. But of this species of poetry, as we have said, one division is assimilative, which is extended to 200 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON rectitude of imitation, but the other is phan- tastic, and affords apparent imitation alone." * Proclus then shows that Plato mentions these kinds of poetry and that Homer was skilled in them all, especially the enthusiastic variety. He concludes by stating that the reason why Plato was so severe on Homer was that in Plato's time poetry was overestimated and philosophy undervalued.2 In Proclus, then, is found the highest justification of poetry and its intimate alliance with the prin ciples of Platonism. Corresponding to the three principles are three kinds of poetry. Emerson had marked this dissertation of Proclus' in his own copy. It gave an account of poetry quite in keeping with his sentiments. And although he does not follow Proclus in the details of his comparison, Emerson is one with him in correlating the method of poetry with that of philosophy. Emerson places the poet on an equal with the man of action and the man of knowledge. The three form a trinity of persons distinct yet equal in power. "For the Universe," he writes, "has three children, born at one time, 1 Quoted in The Works of Plato, translated by Thomas Taylor, I., 438, note. 2 Ibid., note, 439 et sq. ART 201 which reappear under different names in every system of thought, whether they be called cause, operation and effect; or, more poetically, Jove, Pluto, Neptune; or, theo logically, the Father, the Spirit and the Son; but which we will call here the Knower, the Doer and the Sayer. These stand respec tively for the love of truth, for the love of good, and for the love of beauty. These three are equal. Each is that which he is, essen tially, so that he cannot be surmounted or analyzed, and each of these three has the power of the others latent in him and his own, patent." 1 This basic principle which defines the re lation of the poet to a general scheme of things is an amplification of the familiar Platonic doctrine of the trinity of the beautiful, the good, and the true. Emerson's treatment of it here is reminiscent of a discussion in Cud- worth. In his treatment of the pagan deities Cudworth points out how one group of their gods makes up "one orderly and harmonious system of the whole ; one of those gods ruling only in the heavens, another in the sea, and an other in the earth and hell ; one being the god or goddess of learning and wisdom, another of 1 Complete Works, III., 6-7. 202 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON speech and eloquence, another of justice and political order." 1 The reference in the first group is to Jupiter, Neptune, and Pluto, who Cudworth adds, "were not three really dis tinct substantial beings, but only so many sev eral names for one supreme God." 2 From the second group in Cudworth, Emerson got his series, the Knower, the Sayer, and the Doer. And the identification of the three with the primary conception of love of truth, love of beauty, and love of good, shows how the principles of Platonism were the guiding factors in Emerson's thinking. To justify the poet as the representative sayer, or namer of things, Emerson explains the poet's insight into the symbolical nature of the universe. The materials of his craft are symbols. "Nature offers all her creatures to him as a picture language. Being used as a type, a second wonderful value appears in the object, far better than its old value; as the carpenter's stretched cord, if you hold your ear close enough, is musical in the breeze. 'Things more excellent than every image,' says Jamblichus, 'are expressed through images.' Things admit of being used as sym- 1 The True Intellectual System of the Universe, I., 364. »/&«., II, 223. ART 203 bols because nature is a symbol, in the whole, and in every part." 1 This conception of the poet is a growth out of Emerson's familiar way of looking at na ture as a symbol, which truth he had learned in his study of Platonism. The quotation of lamblichus, too, points to the character of the idea; it is a sentiment which lamblichus uses in explaining the true nature of a sacred in stitution, which he says "imitates both the in telligible and celestial order of the Gods; and contains the eternal measures of beings, and those admirable signatures which are sent hither from the Demiurgus and father of wholes, by which things of an ineffable nature are unfolded into light through arcane sym bols, things formless are vanquished by forms, things more excellent than every image are ex pressed through images. . * ." 2 The material of the poet's craft being sym bols, the poet is the man who knows how to articulate them. All men, whether con sciously or not, love symbols and use them but "the poet, by an ulterior intellectual percep tion, gives them a power which makes their old use forgotten, and puts eyes and a tongue into 1 Complete Works, III., 13. 2 On the Mysteries, 79-80. 204 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON every dumb and inanimate object. He per ceives the independence of the thought on the symbol, the stability of the thought, the acci- dency and the f ugacity of the symbol. As the eyes of Lyncaeus were said to see through the earth, so the poet turns the world to, glass, and shows us all things in their right series and procession. For through that better percep tion he stands one step nearer to things, and sees the flowing or metamorphosis ; perceives that thought is multiform; that within the form of every creature is a force impelling it to ascend into a higher form; and following with his eyes the life, uses the forms which ex press that life, and so his speech flows with the flowing of nature. . . . He uses forms according to the life and not according to the form. This is true science. ... By vir tue of this science the poet is the Namer or Language-maker, naming things sometimes after their appearance, sometimes after their essence, and giving to every one its own name and not another's, thereby rejoicing the intel lect, which delights in detachment or bound ary." l In such a theory Platonism plays its part by giving the idea of flux, which Emerson inter- 1 Complete Works, III., 20-21. ART 205 prets in characteristic wise as an ascension. His theory also recalls Plato's discussion of language in the Gratylus. Here is found the mention of an original legislator who is rep resented as naming things, some according to the flux of things, and others according to stability. The majority of words seem to in dicate flux, says Plato, but there are other names "from which," he adds, "one would imagine, that the founder of names did not in dicate things going on and borne along, but such as have an abiding." 1 And finally in identifying poetry with true science, Emer son presents an ideal of the poet very like that ideal which Porphyry says Plotinus repre sented. "Plotinus likewise applied himself," Porphyry writes, "to the canons concerning the stars, but not according to a very mathemat ical mode. That is, we may presume, he very little regarded the calculation of eclipses, or measuring the distance of the sun and moon from the earth, or determining the magni tudes and velocities of the planets. For he considered employments of this kind, as more the province of the mathematician, than of the profound and intellectual philosopher. The mathematical sciences are indeed the proper 1 Bohn translation, III., 388. 206 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON means of acquiring wisdom, but they ought never to be considered as its end. They are the bridge, as it were, between sense and in tellect, by which we may safely pass through the night of oblivion, over the dark and stormy ocean of matter, to the lucid regions of the intelligible world. And he who is de sirous of returning to his true country, will speedily pass over this bridge without making any needless delays in his passage." 1 Such a conception agrees well with Emer son's encomium of the poet. "The poet alone knows astronomy, chemistry, vegetation and animation, for he does not stop at these facts, but employs them as signs. He knows why the plain or meadow of space was strown with flowers we call suns and moons and stars ; why the great deep is adorned with animals, with men, and gods ; for in every word he speaks he rides on them as the horses of thought." 2 In referring to Lyncaeus to explain the acuteness of the poet's spiritual vision Emer son shows indebtedness to Plotinus. In ex plaining the relation of each thing in the in telligible world to the whole Plotinus writes : 1 Select Works, Introduction, liii-liv. Cf. Complete Works, III., 298, note to p. 21. 2 Complete Works, III., 21. ART 207 "For it appears indeed as a part; but by him whose sight is acute, it will be seen as a whole ; viz., by him whose sight resembles that which Lynceus is said to have possessed, and which penetrated the interior parts of the earth; the fable obscurely indicating the acuteness of the vision of supernal eyes." 1 Recollecting this passage, which he had marked in his own copy, Emerson writes: "As the eyes of Lyncaeus were said to see through the earth, so the poet turns the world to glass, and shows us all things in their right series and pro cession." This application to the poet of what the Platonists had said about the philosopher is illustrated in Emerson's further appropri ations from his reading. "Our best definition of poetry," he writes, "is one of the oldest sentences, and claims to come down to us from the Chaldean Zoroaster, who wrote it thus: Toets are standing transporters, whose em ployment consist in speaking to the Father and to matter; in producing apparent imita tions of unapparent natures, and inscribing things unapparent in the apparent fabrica tion of the world ;' in other words, the world 1 Select Works, Introduction, Ixxxi. 2 Complete Works, III., 20. 208 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON exists for thought; it is to make appear things which hide; mountains, crystals, animals, are seen : that which makes them is not seen : these, then, are 'apparent copies of unapparent na tures.' This quotation, which Emerson includes in a list of generalizations that "all have a kind of filial retrospect to Plato and the Greeks," 2 is from Taylor's Collection of Chaldean Oracles, where connection of the oracle with the poets is in no wise intimated. In the original form it reads: "Rulers who under stand the intelligible works of the Father. These he spreads like a veil over sensible works and bodies. They are standing trans porters, whose employment consists in speak ing to the Father and to matter; in producing apparent imitations of unapparent natures; and in inscribing things unapparent in the ap parent fabrication of the world." 3 Poetry and philosophy, then, are one; but with a difference. "Whilst the poet ani mates nature with his own thoughts," Emerson observes in distinguishing them, "he differs 1 Ibid., VIII., 19. a/Md., V., 241. 8 Classical Journal, XVII., 250. ART 209 from the philosopher only herein, that the one proposes Beauty as his main end; the other Truth. . . . The true philosopher and the true poet are one, and a beauty, which is truth, and a truth, which is beauty, is the aim of both." l In support of such a theory Emerson ap peals to the identity in charm of a definition in philosophy and a work of art, such as Sophocles' Antigone.2 "I will not now con sider," he writes, "how much this makes the charm of algebra and the mathematics, which also have their tropes, but it is felt in every definition: as ... when Plato defines a line to be a flowing point; or figure to be a bound of solid. . . . When Socrates, in Charmides, tells us that the soul is cured of its maladies by certain incantations, and that these incantations are beautiful reasons, from which temperance is generated in souls; when Plato calls the world an animal, and Timaeus affirms that the plants also are animals; or affirms a man to be a heavenly tree, growing with his root, which is his head, upward; . . . when Orpheus speaks of hoariness 1 Complete Works, L, 55. 2 Ibid. 210 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON as 'that white flower which marks extreme old age' ; when Proclus calls the universe the statue of the intellect. . . ." 1 This use of symbols in poetry as well as philosophy, has a certain power of exhilaration for all men. "Poets are thus liberating Gods." 2 In thus characterizing them Emer son is alluding to one of the technical terms common in the writings of the Platonists. In the Platonists the term is "liberated gods," and refers to an order of gods, "who," so Taylor in forms us, "are called supercelestial, as being immediately above the mundane gods." 3 They are also the "azonic" gods of which Emerson elsewhere speaks.4 In describing the character of poetic in spiration Emerson makes a further indentifi- cation of the poet with the philosopher. "It is a secret which every intellectual man quickly learns," Emerson explains, "that be yond the energy of his possessed and conscious intellect he is capable of a new energy (as of an intellect doubled on itself), by abandon ment to the nature of things; that beside his 1 Complete Works, III., 30-31. 2 Ibid., 30. 8 Proclus, Commentaries on the Timceus of Plato, II., 12, note 7. * Complete Works, VII., 203. ART 211 privacy of power as an individual man, there is a great public power on which he can draw, by unlocking, at all risks, his human doors, and suffering the ethereal tides to roll and cir culate through him; then he is caught up into the life of the Universe, his speech is thunder, his thought is law, and his words are univer sally intelligible as the plants and animals." * In thus speaking, Emerson is giving his ver sion of the way in which the Platonists main tain the intellect perceives the One in ecstasy. Plotinus writes of this experience: "Hence it is requisite, that the soul of him who ascends to the good should then become intellect, and that he should commit his soul to, and estab lish it in intellect, in order, that what intellect sees, his soul may vigilantly receive, and may through intellect survey the one; not employ ing any one of the senses, nor receiving any thing from them, but with a pure intellect, and with the summit [and as it were, flower] of intellect, beholding that which is most pure."2 And again Plotinus writes: "In tellect possesses a two fold power; one, by which it perceives intellectually, and beholds the form which it contains ; but the other by id., III., 26-27. 2 Select Works, 476-477. 212 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON which it sees things beyond itself by a cer tain intuition and reception. . . . And the former, indeed, is the vision of intellect re plete with wisdom; but the latter, of intellect inflamed with love. For when it becomes in sane through being intoxicated with nectar, then it also becomes amatory." 1 In Emerson the same or similar expressions occur. "The poet knows that he speaks adequately then only when he speaks somewhat wildly, or, 'with the flower of the mind;' not with the intellect used as an organ, but with the intel lect released from all service and suffered to take its direction from its celestial life; or as the ancients were wont to express themselves, not with intellect alone but with the intellect inebriated by nectar." 2 And just as Emerson found in Zoroaster's Oracles a definition for poetry, so he is able to make him explain the nature of the poet's ecstasy. "It is remarkable," he observes, "that we have, out of the deeps of antiquity in the oracles ascribed to the half fabulous Zoroaster, a statement of this fact which every lover and seeker of truth will recognize. 'It is not proper,' said Zoroaster, 'to understand 1 On Suicide, 98. 2 Complete Works, III., 27. ART 213 the Intelligible with vehemence, but if you in cline your mind, you will apprehend it: not too earnestly, but bringing a pure and inquir ing eye. You will not understand it as when understanding some particular thing, but with the flower of the mind. Things divine are not attainable by mortals who understand sensual things, but only the light-armed ar rive at the summit." * In Taylor's Collection of Chaldean Oracles this oracle is given in three separate extracts, (i) "You will not apprehend it by an intellec tual energy, as when understanding some par ticular thing." (2) "It is not proper to under stand that intelligible with vehemence, but with the extended flame of an extended in tellect; a flame which measures all things, ex cept that intelligible. But it is requisite to understand this. For if you incline your mind, you will understand it though not ve hemently. It becomes you therefore, bring ing with you the pure convertible eye of your soul, to extend the void intellect to the intelli gible that you may learn its nature, because it has a subsistence above intellect." 2 In a note to this is added: "This is spoken of a divine 1 Ibid., I., 213-214. 2 Classical Journal, XVI., 133. 214 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON intelligible which is only to be apprehended by the flower of intellect, or, in other words, the unity of the soul." 1 (3) Again the Oracles read : "Things divine cannot be ob tained by those whose intellectual eye is di rected to body; but those only can arrive at the possession of them, who, stript of their gar ments, hasten to the summit." 2 The assem bling of this material and the pruning of the verbiage show how carefully Emerson had read the passages. To explain the nature of inspiration Emer son draws on other quotations £rom his fa vorite books. As to the conditions of in spiration, he refers to Plato. "Plato, in his seventh epistle," he writes, "notes that the per ception is only accomplished by long famil iarity with the objects of intellect, and a life according to the things themselves. 'Then a light, as is leaping from a fire, will on a sud den be enkindled in the soul, and will then it self nourish itself.' " 3 And again he quotes from Plato, this time from the Phcedrus, to the effect that "The man who is his own mas- 1 Ibid., note 2. *Ibid.t XVII., 258. 3 Complete Works, VIII., 274. Cf. Bohn translation of Plato, IV., 524, and Select Works of Plotinus, Introduction, lix, note. ART 215 ter knocks in vain at the doors of poetry." 1 It is quite evident, then, that in his defini tion of poetry, of its materials, and of its in spiration, Emerson is identifying the poet with the philosopher. A further parallel be tween the two is seen in Emerson's conception of true poetic rhymes. By rhymes Emerson does not mean the chime of word with word but rather the bal ance of antagonistic elements composing the universe. Impressed with it in his view of the world, he makes it one of the duties of the poet to attend to such balancings in nature. Thus he has the pine tree in JVoodnotes sing of these.2 Merlin, a name for his ideal poet, attends to recording such rhymes.3 Seyd, an other name for the same poet, had an ear at tuned to them.4 And in his critical discussion of rhyme Emerson points out how true poetic rhyme rises to this as its highest form. "Of course rhyme soars and refines with the growth of mind. The boy liked the drum, the people liked an overpowering jewsharp tune. Later they like to transfer that rhyme to life, and to detect a melody as prompt and perfect in their 1 Complete Works, VIII., 274. 2/Wrf., IX., 54. *Ibid., 120. ., 276. 2i6 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON daily affairs. Omen and coincidence show the rhythmical structure of man; hence the taste for signs, sortilege, prophecy and ful filment, anniversaries, etc. By and by, when they apprehend real rhymes, namely, the cor respondence of parts in Nature — acid and alkali, body and mind, man and maid, char acter and history, action and reaction — they do not longer value rattles and ding-dongs, or barbaric word-jingle. Astronomy, Botany, Chemistry, Hydraulics and the elemental forces have their own periods and returns, their own grand strains of harmony not less exact, up to the primeval apothegm that 'there is nothing on earth which is not in the heavens in a heavenly form, and nothing in the heavens which is not on the earth in an earthly form.' They furnish the poet with grander pairs and alternations, and will require an equal expansion in his metres." 1 This notion is the Pythagorean one of the dualism underlying nature which is a har mony of antagonistic elements. The Plato- nists incorporated it into their thought and Emerson uses it as the basic principle of his doctrine of Compensation. Its source in the Platonists is also indicated in Emerson's quo- i Ibid., VIII., 4&-49- ART 217 tation of "the primeval apothegm." This is an adaptation of the Smaragdine Table "which is of such great authority with the alchemists," says Taylor, "and which whether originally written or not by Hermes Tris- megistus, is doubtless of great antiquity." * Emerson's quotation is not an exact but a free rendering of its opening words: "It is true without a lie, certain, and most true, that what is beneath is like that which is above, and what is above is like that which is be neath, for the purpose of accomplishing the miracle of one thing." 2 The doctrine of Platonism which this expresses is given by Plotinus who holds that all things pre-exist ideally in the intelligible world. By blend ing the notion of parallelism with that of an tagonism Emerson comes to view the relation of the world of sense to the world of pure in tellect as one of the great rhymes to which the poet will attend. After this analysis of Emerson's canons of art it appears that in this realm he expected to find the fruition of his deepest desires as a philosopher. In the artist he sees the work- 1 Quoted in Proclus, On the Theology of Plato, I., 194, note. 2i 8 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON ing of the Universal Mind and in the poet, the supreme artist, he finds one who is working with the materials and in the manner of the inquiring spirit of a philosopher. "Of course,'7 he fails not to add, "when we de scribe man as poet, and credit him with the triumphs of the art, we speak of the potential or ideal man — not found now in any one per son. You must go through a city or a nation, and find one faculty here, one there, to build the true poet withal. Yet all men know the portrait when it is drawn, and it is part of re ligion to believe its possible incarnation. He is the healthy, the wise, the fundamental, the manly man, seer of the secret; against all the appearance he sees and reports the truth, namely, that the soul generates matter. And poetry is the only verity — the expression of a sound mind speaking after the ideal, and not after the apparent." l It is the poet-philosopher to whom Emer son looks for the long promised ideal that Nature has been striving to perfect. As ap proximations to that ideal, Emerson alludes to a few men among whom Plato and Plotinus are found. Thus Nature in her song says : i Complete Works, VIII., 26-27. ART 219 "Twice I have moulded an image, And thrice outstretched my hand, Made one of day and one of night And one of the salt sea-sand. "One in Judaean manger, And one by Avon stream, One 1 over against the mouths of Nile, And one 2 in the Academe." 3 But Emerson's ideal is manifestly unfair to art, for it expects art to do more than it ought. It lacks balance and sanity of judgment and shows an incapacity to do justice to the sensu ous as well as the spiritual side of the subject. No better indication of the glaring defects of Emerson's appreciative criticism can be found than in his statement that "perhaps Homer and Milton will be tin pans yet. Better not to be easily pleased. The poet should rejoice if he has taught us to despise his song; if he has so moved us as to lift us — to open the eye of the intellect to see farther and better." 4 This extreme is matched by his high estimate of Proclus. Speaking of his intellectual 1 Plotinus. 2 Plato. 3 Complete Works, IX., 246. ., VIIL, 68. 220 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON strength, Emerson told his auditors in his Harvard course on philosophy, "What lit erature should be, he is." 1 His identification of the poet with the philosopher thus ends in the banishment of the poet. In this respect Emerson forsakes Plotinus and goes over to Plato, although his method of reasoning is not that employed by Plato. It is due to the fact that Emerson did not check in himself the strong ascetic tendency fostered by reading in the philosophy of Plotinus; which tendency Plotinus himself had resisted in his valuation of sensuous beauty. 1 Atlantic Monthly, LL, 827. CHAPTER VI MYTHOLOGY PLATO has the distinction of being the poet-philosopher among the thinkers of the world. He had a mind that laid the foundations for pure speculative metaphysics and at the same time he was gifted with an imagination that so blended itself with his most abstruse thinking that it is difficult to separate his science from his metaphors. And these in the extended form of myths or apologues have such brilliancy of their own that they make the reading of Plato an en joyment such as only poetry in its highest flights can afford. His myth of the charioteer and the two horses in the Phcedrus, the narra tive of Er the son of Armenius in the Re public, the figure of the cave in the same dia logue, the myths concerning the origin of love in the Banquet — merely to mention a few ex amples — have imprinted themselves in the hu man memory, as Emerson observes, like the signs of the zodiac. Thus a study of the in- 221 222 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON fluence of Platonism must attend to the imagi native side of Plato's art as well as to his phil osophical teaching. This is especially true of a study of Emerson's Platonism, for his was a temperament in which imagination was highly developed. Feeding naturally on the doctrines of Platonism, he was influenced by Plato's manner of using myths or fables to set forth his teachings. In The American Scholar Emerson uses a fable to convey his leading conception — the nature of the scholar. "It is one of those fables," he writes, "which out of an unknown antiquity convey an unlooked-for wisdom, that the gods, in the beginning, divided Man into men, that he might be more helpful to himself; just as the hand was divided into fin gers, the better to answer its end. The old fable covers a doctrine ever new and sublime ; that there is One Man — present to all partic ular men only partially, or through one faculty; and that you must take the whole so ciety to find the whole man." 1 The source of this fable is to be found in Plato's Banquet. There Aristophanes tells of the nature of original men: "The entire form of every individual of the human race 1 Complete Works, L, 82. MYTHOLOGY 223 was rounded, having the back and sides as in a circle. It had four hands, and legs equal in number to the hands ; and two faces upon the circular neck, alike in every way, and one head on both the faces placed opposite, and four ears . . . and from these it is easy to conjecture how all the other parts were doubled." 1 Such mortals were terrible in force — the narrative proceeds — and became so threatening in their attempts to attack the gods in heaven that Jupiter determined to halve them in order to weaken their strength. Tay lor in a note to his translation refers to the fable as one "which I doubt not is of greater antiquity than Plato." 2 With this fable Emerson blends an account of the use of brothers which Plutarch gives in his essay, Of Brotherly Love. "And Nature hath given us very near examples of the use of brothers, by contriving most of the necessary parts of our bodies double, as it were, brothers and twins — as hands, feet, ears, nostrils — thereby telling us that all these were thus dis tinguished for mutual benefit and assistance, and not for variance and discord. And when she parted the very hands into many and un- iBohn translation, III., 508-509. 2 The Works of Plato, III., 475, note I. 224 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON equal fingers, she made them thereby the most curious and artificial of all our mem bers; in so much that the ancient philosopher Anaxagoras assigned the hands for the reason of all human knowledge and discretion. But the contrary seems the truth. For it is not man's having hands that makes him the wisest animal, but his being naturally reasonable and capable of art was the reason why such organs were conferred upon him. And this also is most manifest to every one, that the reason why Nature out of one seed and source formed two, three, and more brethren was not for dif ference and opposition, but that their being apart might render them the more capable of assisting one another. For those that were treble-bodied and hundred-handed, if any such there were, while they had all their mem bers joined to each other could do nothing without them or apart." 1 From Plato, then, Emerson got the idea of the gods dividing man into men; from Plu tarch came the reason for the division, namely, to make man more helpful to himself; and from the same source came the simile of the di vision of the hands into fingers. Taylor's note 1 Plutarch, Morals, III., 37. MYTHOLOGY 225 formed the basis for the assignment of the fable to an unknown antiquity. Emerson's own mind fused these elements into a version quite his own. He uses it to point the moral he is inculcating; that in the various occupa tions in which in the divided or social state men are engaged, it is man acting now in one function, now in another; in no one is the en tire man but only a part of him. Hence he treats the scholar, his topic in hand, as man thinking. It is an idea that suggests the doc trine of Universal Mind; but that is present entire to each man, whereas the One Man is present to all particular men only partially, or through one faculty. Emerson, however, ap plies the doctrine in a way that shows the theory to be identical with his doctrine of Universal Mind. "It is remarkable," he ob serves, "the character of the pleasure we de rive from the best books. They impress us with the conviction that one nature wrote and the same reads •.. . . But for the evidence thence afforded to the philosophical doctrine of the identity of all minds, we should suppose some pre-established harmony, some foresight of souls that were to be, and some preparation of stores for their future wants, like the fact 226 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON observed in insects, who lay up food before death for the young grub they shall never see." 1 It is to be noted, however, that in one place Emerson refers this fable of One Man to Seneca. Speaking of the coldness of Seneca's virtue, he qualifies by adding, "Yet what noble words we owe to him: (God divided man into men, that they might help each other.' " 2 But the fable does not appear in Seneca. Emerson may have been led to assign it to him by recollecting the caption of one of Seneca's Epistles (XVII), which in his own copy reads: "The Original of all men is the same." 3 The error in assigning the fable to Seneca is not alone in Emerson's practice. In his Nature he assigns to Plato the sentence — "poetry comes nearer to vital truth than his tory" ; but it belongs to Aristotle.4 He makes Plotinus say "the knowledge of the senses is truly ludicrous";5 but it is a quotation from Proclus's treatise On Providence and Fate, 1 Complete Works, I., 91-92. 2 Ibid., X., 312. 8 Seneca's Morals by way of Abstract, by Roger L'Es- trange, 336. * Complete Works, I., 69. Cf. S. H. Butcher, Aristotle's Theory of Poetry and Fine Art, 35. 5 Complete Works, X., 281. MYTHOLOGY 227 where in Emerson's own copy the passage is marked by his own hand.1 He also refers to Plato's cave in the Republic as the "cave of Trophonius," which is the cave mentioned by Plutach.2 It is not strange then, that writing as Emerson did late in life, he should have as signed to Seneca what he had previously gath ered from Plutarch and Plato. Emerson uses the fable of the Sphinx to ex plain one of Plato's teachings. "As near and proper to us," he writes, "is also that old fable of the Sphinx, who was said to sit on the road side and put riddles to every passenger. If the man could solve the riddle, the Sphinx was slain. What is our life but an endless flight of winged facts or events? In splendid variety these changes come, all putting ques tions to the human spirit. Those men who cannot answer by a superior wisdom these facts or questions of time, serve them. Facts encumber them, tyrannize over them, and make the men of routine the men of sense, in whom a literal obedience to facts has extin guished every spark of that light by which man is truly man. But if the man is true to 1 On the Theology of Plato, II., 472. 2 Complete Works, IV., 83. Cf. Plutarch's Lives, trans lated by John and William Langhorne, II., 293; III., 141. 228 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON his better instincts or sentiments, and refuses the dominion of facts, as one that comes of a higher race ; remains fast by the soul and sees the principle, then the facts fall aptly and sup ple into their places; they know their master, and the meanest of them glorifies him." 1 The poetical rendering of this idea is found in his poem, The Sphinx. There Emerson explains how the poet solves the secret which the Sphinx has been keeping for ages. This secret concerns the condition of man who seems to stand quite apart from the other members of creation. These share the eternal peace of the universe: "But man crouches and blushes Absconds and conceals; He creepeth and peepeth He palters and steals; Infirm, melancholy, Jealous glancing around, An oaf, an accomplice, He poisons the ground. " With this difference in mind the Sphinx asks the question which the great mother Nature has put: 1 Complete Works, II., 32-33. MYTHOLOGY 229 " 'Who has drugged my boy's cup ? Who has mixed my boy's bread? Who with sadness and madness Has turned my child's head?' ' The poet is the man who answers the ques tion. Thus Emerson explains how the poet says to the Sphinx : "The fiend that man harries Is love of the Best; Yawns the pit of the Dragon, Lit by rays from the Blest. The Lethe of Nature Can't trance him again, Whose soul sees the perfect, Which his eyes seek in vain. "To vision profounder Man's spirit must dive ; His aye-rolling orb At no goal will arrive." 1 This eternal search on the part of man for the attainment of a vision ever receding is symbolical of the truth which Plato lays down 1 Complete Works, IX., 22-23. 23o THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON as the distinguishing characteristic of man. In the Phcedrus he says that "it is necessary that a man should understand according to a generic form, as it is called, which proceeding from many perceptions is by reasoning com bined into one." 1 Or as Emerson renders the passage, "the essence or peculiarity of man is to comprehend a whole; or that which in the diversity of sensations can be comprised under a rational unity." 2 On the other hand, according to Emerson, who still quotes from the Phcedrus, "the soul which has never per ceived the truth, cannot pass into human form." 3 The suggestion to use the fable of the Sphinx to set forth this teaching of Plato arose in Emerson's mind after he had read Taylor's note explaining the meaning of the fable. This note occurs on a passage in the extract from Synesius On Providence, ap pended to Taylor's translation of the Select Works of Plotinus. Emerson indicated the passage in his own copy by inserting at the place a slip of paper on which "Sphinx" was inscribed and by noting the passage under that 1 Bohn translation, I., 325. 2 Complete Works, IV., 63. *Ibid. Cf. Bohn translation, I., 325- MYTHOLOGY 231 heading in his index. "It appears to me," the note reads, "that the ancients, by the sphinx designed to represent to us the nature of the phantasy or imagination. In order to be convinced of which, it is necessary to ob serve that the rational soul, or the true man, consists of intellect, dianoia or the discursive energy of reason, and opinion; but the fic titious man, or the irrational soul, commences from the phantasy, under which desire and anger subsist. Hence, the basis of the ra tional life is opinion, but the summit of the irrational life is phantasy. . . . But the riddles of the sphinx are images of the obscure and intricate nature of the phantasy. He, therefore, who is unable to solve the riddles of the sphinx, i. e., who cannot comprehend the dark and perplexed nature of the phantasy, will be drawn into her embraces and torn in pieces; viz., the phantasy in such a one will subject to its power the rational life, cause its indivisible energies to become divisible, and thus destroy as much as possible its very es sence." 1 With the idea expressed in this note Emer son's conception of man as a thinking being who seeks principles beneath facts easily 1 Select Works, 539, note i. 232 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON blended. The opposition between one who attends only to facts and one who grasps prin ciples passes over to the opposition between phantasy or imagination, the highest form of the perception of sensible things, and intellect, which is a faculty of the soul superior to sense perception. With this new pair of opposing elements Emerson identifies the Sphinx and the Poet respectively. Taylor had explained the equivalence of phantasy and the Sphinx and Emerson was but expressing his own idea when he makes the poet representative of in tellect. Such an explanation does not strain the poem. In his prose account of the fable Em erson, holding to the common interpretation, says that the Sphinx sitting by the roadside "puts riddles to every passenger"; but in the poem the Sphinx herself is perplexed. She is pictured drowsy and brooding on. the world; her first words are : "Who'll tell me my secret, The ages have kept? I awaited the seer While they slumbered and slept." And the specific question she puts is that which she had heard from Nature, the great MYTHOLOGY 233 mother, who is inquiring concerning the secret of man's condition. And the reason why the Sphinx is unable to answer the ques tion can be inferred from the Poet's words to her: "Dull Sphinx, Jove keep thy five wits; Thy sight is growing blear; Rue, myrrh, cummin for the Sphinx Her muddy eyes to clear!" Such a characterization points to phantasy as the function of the soul which the Sphinx rep resents. The five wits all feed imagination, or phantasy. And the Sphinx acknowledges as much to the poet. "The old Sphinx bit her thick lip- Said, 'Who taught thee me to name?' I am thy spirit, yoke-fellow ; Of thine eye I am eyebeam." That is, phantasy, or imagination, is the yoke fellow of the poet. The union of phantasy and intellect as necessary factors in the soul's life is here indicated. It thus appears that only by following the explanation of Taylor, that is, by identifying the Sphinx with phan tasy, or imagination, that we can come to 234 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON understand what Emerson is aiming at in his poem. This explanation also gives meaning to cer tain details which otherwise would remain meaningless. In Emerson's prose version of the myth we read that if one was able to solve the secret, the Sphinx was slain. Taylor's note, however, explains this as follows: "But he who, like CEdipus, is able to solve the enig mas of the sphinx, or, in other words, to com prehend the dark essence of his phantasy, will, by illuminating its obscurity with the light of intellect, cause it, by becoming lucid through out, to be no longer what it was before." l And again: "Her [phantasy's] wings are images of the elevating powers, which the phantasy naturally possesses; for it is re-ele vated in conjunction with the returning soul, to the region everyway resplendent with divine light." 2 In other words, phantasy when intellect functions properly is elevated and shines with a light imparted by intellect. Or as Emerson renders the change: "Uprose the merry Sphinx And crouched no more in stone; 1 Select Works, 540, note i. MYTHOLOGY 235 She melted into purple cloud, She silvered in the moon; She spired into a yellow flame; She flowered in blossoms red; She flowed into a foaming wave; She stood Monadnoc's head." That is, the imagination of the poet when illuminated by intellect uses things as sym bols, thus translating earthly things into higher power. It is fitting, then, that Emerson should give the last part of his poem over to Nature. It is she that had originally asked the question; the Sphinx got it from her. And so the poem properly ends with the sanction which Na ture gives to the truth that the Poet has spoken. "Through a thousand voices Spoke the universal dame; 'Who telleth one of my meanings Is master of all I am/ ' The sentiment is that of the microcosm. Another myth which Emerson uses to point a meaning is one which he found in his Bohn edition of Plato. There in a note to a passage in Sisyphus, a pseudo-Platonic dia logue, he read of "an ^Esopo-Socratic fable," 236 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON which the editor says was "first published in a latent metrical form by De Furia, from a Vatican MS., but recently in a more complete state from an Athos MS. by Boissonade." The English version of it runs : "To the gods Apollo, his long arrows holding, Spoke thus — Who knows the arrow to let fly, Than the far-darting farther? On the strife With Phoebus enter'd Zeus, his weapons handling. In Ares' helmet Hermes shook the lots, Which Phoebus first obtaining, with his hands The bent bow pushing from him, and the string Letting go sharply, first his arrow fix'd Within the distant gardens of the West. When with his stride did Zeus the distance clear, And cried — Where shall I shoot? no space have I. And no bow drawing, bow-man's glory gained." l Emerson uses this fable to illustrate the superiority of character over talent. "It is a fine fable," he writes, "for the advantage of character over talent, the Greek legend of the strife of Jove and Phoebus. Phoebus chal lenged the gods, and said, Who will outshoot the far darting Apollo?' Zeus said, 'I will.' Mars shook the lots in his helmet, and that of Apollo leaped out first. Apollo stretched 1 The Works of Plato, Bohn translation, VI, 107, note 3. MYTHOLOGY 237 his bow and shot his arrow into the extreme west. Then Zeus rose, and with one stride cleared the whole distance, and said, 'Where shall I shoot? there is no space left.' So the bowman's prize was adjudged to him who drew no bow." 1 In his poem, Uriel, Emerson uses a bit of mythology of his own creation. It tells of the lapse of the archangel Uriel from his high state due to his bold philosophy of the good. The meaning of the fable is best understood when viewed in its relation to Emerson's Platonism. Emerson held to the essential goodness of all things, including what we usually call evil. "I own I am gladdened by seeing the predominance of the saccharine principle throughout vegetable nature, and not less by beholding in morals that unrestrained inun dation of the principle of good into every chink and hole that selfishness has left open, yea into selfishness and sin itself; so that no evil is pure, nor hell itself without its extreme satisfactions." 2 "Thus a sublime confidence is fed at the bottom of the heart that, in spite of appearances, in spite of malignity and * Complete Works, VII., 184. tf., II., 3I7-3I& 238 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON blind self-interest living for the moment, an eternal, beneficent necessity is always bring ing things right; and though we should fold our arms — which we cannot do, for our duty requires us to be the very hands of this guid ing sentiment, and work in the present mo ment — the evils we suffer will at last end themselves through the incessant opposition of Nature to everything hurtful." 1 This is a doctrine which Emerson found in Platonism. "Evil according to old phi losophers," he tells us, "is good in the mak ing." 2 It is to the Platonists that he refers. "Every part, indeed, of this mundane fabric and drama," says Proclus, "has for its end good; since no part of it is left inordinate; but it is so woven with other parts, as to con tribute to the well being of the universe." 3 And in his own copy of the Select Works of Plotinus he has indexed under "Good of Evil" a passage from Plato quoted in a note by Taylor. "Conformably to this, it is di vinely said by Plato in the Republic: 'What ever comes from the Gods to the man who is beloved by the Gods, will all be the best possi- 1 Ibid., X., 188-189. 2 Ibid., IV., 138. 3 On Providence and Fate, in On the Theology of Plato, II., 466. MYTHOLOGY 239 ble, unless he has some necessary ill from former miscarriage. Hence, if the just man happens to be in poverty or disease, or in any other of those seeming evils, these things issue to him in something good either alive or dead.' " 1 It is this doctrine that the archangel Uriel refers to when he expressed the sentiment that caused his lapse. " 'Line in nature is not found; Unit and universe are round; In vain produced, all rays return; Evil will bless, and ice will burn.' ' And though obscured in his fall, Uriel's voice of scorn was still heard shrilling, "Out of the good of evil born" — a sentiment that filled the old gods with fear. But Emerson owes to Plotinus not only the central idea of the poem, but the manner of its expression. Thus, in explaining himself, Uriel uses symbolical language of line and circle. Such symbolical use of geometrical terms is constant in Plato and the Platonists. "For a right line," Proclus explains, "is im perfect, as always capable of being extended; but a circle and a sphere are most perfect, as 1 Select Works, 361, note I. 240 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON not receiving increase, and as making the end of their motion the beginning." 1 Uriel thus, in giving his sentiment "against the being of a line," was talking the language of Platonism. In fabricating the fable, too, Emerson draws on the notions of Platonism for certain details. Of the time of Uriel's lapse Emer son writes : "It fell in the ancient periods Which the brooding soul surveys, Or ever the wild Time coined itself Into calendar months and days." This conception of time is that of Plato in the Timceus. Time is there defined as an image of eternity and was created by the Demiurgus along with the universe. "But besides this," Plato adds, "he contrived the days and nights, months and years, which had no existence prior to the universe, but rose into being contemporaneously with its forma tion." 2 The time of Uriel's lapse was in that eternal period before time was. Again, the nature of the punishment that Uriel suffers is that frequently referred to by Plato and the Platonists. In Plato the trans- 1 Commentaries on the Timceus of Plato, II., 445. 2Bohn translation, II., 341. MYTHOLOGY 241 migration of the soul is more than once indi cated ; * and in Plotinus the reasons for the lapse of the soul into the world of matter are given. "The assertions, therefore/' Plotinus says, "are by no means discordant with each other, which declare that souls are sown in generation, and that they descend for the sake of causing the perfection of the universe; likewise that they are condemned to suffer punishment, and are confined in a cave." 2 Adopting the hint of the lapse of the soul into the realms of generation and its transmigra tion therein, Emerson says of Uriel: UA sad self-knowledge, withering, fell On the beauty of Uriel; In heaven once eminent, the god Withdrew, that hour, into his cloud; Whether doomed to long gyration In the sea of generation, Or by knowledge grown too bright To hit the nerve of feebler sight." 3 In closing his essay, Manners, Emerson ap pears a second time as an inventor of a fable out of suggestions he found in his Platonic iBohn translation, I., 325; II., 347. 2 Five Books, 270-271. Cf. Complete Works, IX., 410. 3 Complete Works, IX., 114. 242 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON sources. Speaking of the character of human society, he observes : "Too good for banning, and too bad for blessing, it reminds us of a tradition of the pagan mythology, in any at tempt to settle its character. (I overheard Jove, one day,' said Silenus, 'talking of de stroying the earth ; he said it had failed ; they were all rogues and vixens, who went from bad to worse, as fast as the days succeeded each other. Minerva said she hoped not; they were only ridiculous little creatures, with this odd circumstance, that they had a blur, or indeterminate aspect, seen far or seen near; if you called them bad, they would appear so; if you called them good, they would appear so; and there was no one person or action among them which would not puzzle her owl, much more all Olympus, to know whether it was fundamentally bad or good.' " 1 This fable appears to be a presentation in dialogue form of an idea which Emerson noted in his Plutarch. There, in his essay Of Isis and Osiris, in a passage marked by Em erson's own hand, can be read: "For the harmony of the world is (according to Hera- clitus) like that of a bow or a harp, alternately d., in, 155. MYTHOLOGY 243 tightened and relaxed; and according to Euripides, Nor good nor bad here's to be found apart; I But both immixed in one, for greater art. And, therefore, this most ancient opinion hath been handed down from the theologists and law-givers to the poets and philosophers, it having an original fathered upon none, but having gained a persuasion both strong and indelible, and being everywhere professed and received by barbarians as well as Grecians — and that not only in vulgar discourses and public fame, but also in their secret mysteries and open sacrifices — that the world is neither hurried about by wild chance without intelli gence, discourse and direction, nor yet that there is but one reason, which as it were with a rudder or with gentle and easy reins directs it and holds it in; but that, on the contrary, there are in it several differing things, and those made up of bad as well as good; or rather (to speak more plainly) that Nature produces nothing here but what is mixed and tempered." 1 By appropriating this view of the world and assigning characters Emerson 1 Morals, IV., 105-106. 244 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON was able to work out a fable in which he sums up his teaching on the matter in hand. In another instance Emerson expresses a familiar idea of Platonism through a fable which he says "seems somehow to have been dropped from the current mythologies." 1 "Saturn grew weary of sitting alone, or with none but the great Uranus or Heaven be holding him, and he created an oyster. Then he would act again, but he made nothing more, but went on creating the race of oysters. Then Uranus cried, 'A new work, O Saturn 1 the old is not good again.' "Saturn replied, 'I fear. There is not only the alternative of making and not making, but also of unmaking. Seest thou the great sea, how it ebbs and flows? so it is with me; my power ebbs; and if I put forth my hands, I shall not do, but undo. Therefore I do what I have done; I hold what I have got; and so I resist Night and Chaos.' " *O Saturn,' replied Uranus, 'thou canst not hold thine own but by making more. Thy oysters are barnacles and cockles, and with the next flowing of the tide they will be pebbles and sea foam.' " *I see,' rejoins Saturn, 'thou art in league 1 Complete Works, IM 296. MYTHOLOGY 24,5 with Night, thou art become an evil eye; thou spakest from love; now thy words smite me with hatred. I appeal to Fate, must there not be rest?' — 'I appeal to Fate, also/ said Uranus, 'must there not be motion?' — But Saturn was silent, and went on making oysters for a thousand years. "After that, the word of Uranus came into his mind like a ray of the sun, and he made Jupiter; and then he feared again; and nature froze, the things that were made went back ward, and to save the world, Jupiter slew his father Saturn." 1 The fable sets forth the opposition between the principle of motion and the principle of rest. Emerson identifies the one with Inno vation and the other with Conservatism. They are the two principles in accordance with which Plato builds up his conception of the world of matter and of the world of pure ideas; and they were inherited from the Pythagorean speculation on the universe as a harmony of mutually antagonistic elements. It is a familiar idea in Emerson and here he uses Plato's manner of mythologizing in order to express the truth. At the close of his essay on Immortality id., I., 296-297. 246 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON Emerson recounts a fable which he had prob ably met with in one of his Hindoo books.1 It deals with the reluctance of Yama, the lord of Death, to fulfill his promise to Nachiketas, the son of Gautama, which was to grant him three boons of his own choice. Two he willingly granted, but the third, which was a request to unfold the history of the soul after death, Yama at first declines to answer; but Nachiketas growing so importunate, he speaks to him of the eternal nature of the soul. This Indian fable is used by Emerson much in the manner of Plato in his Phcedo, where, after the philosophic discussion on immortality, one of the characters tells a fable of the other world.2 Associated with these fables of Emerson's are his utterances which he assigns to "his Orphic poet." This is no other person than Emerson himself, who is working out a sug gestion he found in Proclus. "He who desires to signify divine concerns through symbols in Orphic," says Proclus, "and, in short, accords with those who write fables concerning the gods." 3 He uses this sugges- i Ibid., VIII., 349-352. 2Bohn translation, L, 117, et sq. 3 On the Theology of Plato, L, 12. MYTHOLOGY 247 tion in his Nature and also in his essay, The Poet, although in this latter reference the poet is not styled Orphic. In Nature this Orphic poet sings some tra ditions of man and nature. Among his utter ances are these words: aMan is the dwarf of himself. Once he was permeated and dis solved by spirit. He filled nature with his overflowing currents. Out from him sprang the sun and moon; from man the sun, from woman the moon. The laws of his mind, the periods of his actions externized themselves into day and night, into year and the seasons. But, having made for himself this huge shell, his waters retired; he no longer fills the veins and veinlets ; he is shrunk to a drop. He sees that the structure still fits him, but fits him colossally. Say, rather, once it fitted him, now it corresponds to him from far and on high. He adores timidly his own work. Now is man the follower of the sun and woman the follower of the moon. Yet some times he starts in his slumber, and wonders at himself and his house, and muses strangely at the resemblance betwixt him and it. He perceives that if his law is still paramount, if still he have elemental power, if his word is sterling yet in nature, it is not conscious 248 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON power, it is not inferior, but superior to his will. It is instinct." * The underlying idea is the familiar one of the mysterious relation of man to nature. In explaining it Emerson had used the doctrines of Platonism, as has already been indicated. But in this instance he has seized upon certain suggestions found in the Platonists and at tempted to work them into a semblance of a tradition or fable. lamblichus gave him the idea that man is but a dwarf of himself. In his Mysteries of the Egyptians, Chaldeans, and Assyrians lam blichus had written: "I say, therefore, that the more divine intelligible man, who was formerly united to the Gods by the vision of them, afterwards entered into another soul, which is coadapted to the human form, and through this became fettered with the bonds of necessity and fate." 2 In Proclus Emerson found the suggestion that out of man sprang the sun and moon. Speaking of the goddess Athena, Proclus says : "But the Egyptians relate, that in the adytum of the Goddess [Athena] there was this in scription : 'I am the things that are, that will 1 Complete Works, I., 71-72. 2 P. 332. MYTHOLOGY 249 be, and that have been. No one has ever laid open the garment by which I am concealed. The fruit which I brought forth was the sun.' " Such a conception is in keeping with the idea that the Platonists held: that visible things are effluxious from the gods. Plu tarch's essay, Of Isis and Osiris, contains many instances of such an interpretation. Emerson himself, in another place, quotes Proclus to the effect that "gold and silver grow7 in the earth from the celestial gods — an effluxion from them." 2 It was natural, then, for him to carry over the idea to man in his former union with the Divine. Nature thus became an effluxion from man's spirit. The idea that man is now a follower of the sun is, perhaps, a recollection of Plutarch's remark: "We appear to be passionately in love with the sun." 3 And the sun, he says, interferes with spiritual vision "by sense with drawing the rational intellect from that which is to that which appears." 4 The suggestion that woman is a follower of the moon may have arisen in Emerson's mind 1 Commentaries on the Timaus of Plato, L, 82. 2 Complete Works, X., 272. * Morals, IV., 294. *Ibid., III., 82. 250 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON as a natural parallel. Perhaps, however, Plutarch's comparison of Venus to the moon in his dialogue, Of Love, may have been in Emerson's thought, especially as it occurs in a passage where the god of love is compared to the Sun.1 If this reasoning be true, and it is not a strained analysis, Emerson's utterances as Orphic poet would be an instance of the truth of the remark he makes on Plutarch — "A poet might rhyme all day with hints drawn from Plutarch, page on page." 2 It thus becomes quite evident that teaching by myth, fable or apologue is a favorite way of Emerson's. Emerson's myths are, of course, much inferior to Plato's in depth and in brilliancy, but they testify to a conscious effort on Emerson's part to follow at a dis tance in the distinctly Platonic manner of blending philosophy and poetry. As was seen in the explanation of the Sphinx, Emerson is careful to rationalize the myths that interested him. It was a practice which Plato himself had used in his searching criticism of the old Greek myths. In the later Platonists myths are frequently ration- rf., IV., 293- 2 Complete Works, X., 301. MYTHOLOGY 251 alized. In his copy of On the Theology of Plato Emerson had indexed a passage, "Mythology," which taught that the "mytho logical mode which indicates divine concerns through conjectures is ancient, concealing truth under a multitude of veils, and pro ceeding in a manner similar to nature, which extends sensible figments of intelligibles, ma terial, of immaterial, partible, of impartible natures, and images, and things which have a false being, of things perfectly true." l Into this habit Emerson himself falls. The myth of Pan held Emerson's attention. He gives it two interpretations. "The my thology," he observes, "cleaves close to Na ture; and what else was it they represented in Pan, god of shepherds, who was not yet com pletely finished in godlike form, blocked rather, and wanting the extremities; had em blematic horns and feet? Pan, that is, All. His habit was to dwell in mountains, lying on the ground, tooting like a cricket in the sun, refusing to speak, clinging to his behemoth ways. He could intoxicate by the strain of his shepherd's pipe — silent yet to most, for his pipes make the music of the spheres, which, because it sounds eternally, is not heard at all 1 On the Theology of Plato, L, 13. 252 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON by the dull, but only by the mind. He wears a coat of leopard spots or stars. He could terrify by earth-born fears called panics Yet was he in the secret of Nature and could look both before and after. He was only seen under disguises, and was not represented by any outward image ; a terror sometimes, at others a placid omnipotence." 1 This account seems to be largely built out of materials Emerson found in Cudworth. In a passage, which Emerson had indexed, "Pan," Cudworth gives a quotation from a Platonist named Phornutus, who thus de scribes Pan: " 'The lower parts of Pan (saith he) were rough and goatish, because of the asperity of the earth; but his upper parts of a human form, because the ether being ra tional and intellectual, is the Hegemonic of the world'; adding hereunto, 'that Pan was feigned ... to be clothed with the skin of a libbard, because of the bespangled heavens, and the beautiful variety of things in the world; to live in a desert, because of the singularity of the world; and, lastly, to be a good demon by reason of the TPO«TTW« afoot \6yo^ that supreme mind, reason, and understand- 1 Complete Works, XII., 35-36. MYTHOLOGY 253 ing, that governs all in it.' " x In a second passage Cudworth adds: "First of all, Pan, as the very word plainly implies him to be a universal Numen, and as he was supposed to be the Harmostes of the whole world, or to play upon the world as a musical instru ment, according to that of Orpheus (or Onomacritus) : 'ApfJLOViaV KOVfJLOLO Kp€Kd)V So have we before showed that by him the Arcadians and Greeks meant, not the cor poreal world inanimate, nor yet as endued with a senseless nature only, but as proceeding from an intellectual principle or divine spirit, which framed it harmoniously; and as being still kept in tune, acted and governed by the same." * And again Cudworth says: "The an cient mythologists represented the nature of the universe by Pan playing upon a pipe or harp ... ; as if nature did, by a silent melody, make all the parts of the universe everywhere dance in measure and proportion, itself being as it were in the meantime de- 1 The True Intellectual System of the Universe, L, 583. uf., II., 208. 254 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON lighted and ravished with the re-echoing of its own harmony." 1 In interpreting this myth, however, Emer son does not follow Cudworth. Cudworth identifies Pan with God; but Emerson sees in the myth either a representation of instinct or of man. "Such homage," he says of it, "did the Greek — delighting in accurate form, not fond of the extravagant and unbounded — pay to the inscrutable force we call Instinct, or Nature when it first becomes intelligent." 2 And in another place he holds: "The great Pan of old, who was clothed in a leopard skin to signify the beautiful variety of things, and the firmament, his coat of stars — was but the representative of thee, O rich and various Man! thou palace of sight and sound, carry ing in thy senses the morning and the night and the unfathomable galaxy; in thy brain, the geometry of the City of God; in thy heart, the bower of love and the realms of right and wrong." 3 In his poetry, however, Emerson adopts the notion of Cudworth that Pan represented God who is infused into all things. Hence, 1 Ibid., I., 242. 2 Complete Works, XII., 36. slbid., I., 205-206. XA f Of THE [ UNIVERSITY ) MYTHOLOGY 255 in the poem, Pan, he uses the idea to set forth his favorite doctrine of the Over-Soul. "O what are heroes, prophets, men, But pipes through which the breath of Pan doth blow A momentary music. Being's tide Swells hitherward, and myriads of forms Live, robed with beauty, painted by the sun; Their dust, pervaded by the nerves of God, Throbs with an overmastering energy Knowing and doing. Ebbs the tide, they lie White hollow shells upon the desert shore, But not the less the eternal wave rolls on To animate new millions, and exhale Races and planets, its enchanted foam." 1 With Cudworth, too, Emerson agrees in the use of the myth of Proteus. In Plato there are several references to that figure as an elusive being, constantly changing form; but it is Cudworth who applies the idea to the ever-changing flux in the world of matter. In a long passage on the eternal change in nature, which Emerson has marked in his own copy, Cudworth says that the "matter of the universe is always substantially the same, and neither more nor less, but only Proteanly •id., IX., 360, 256 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON transformed into different shapes." * And, in like manner, Emerson observes: "The philosophical perception of identity through endless mutations of form makes him know the Proteus. What else am I who laughed or wept yesterday, who slept last night like a corpse, and this morning stood and ran? And what see I on any side but the transmi grations of Proteus?"2 Emerson also adopts the view of the Pla- tonists who see hidden meanings in the defects which are associated with certain mythologi cal characters. "In the old mythology, my- thologists observe," says Emerson, "defects are ascribed to divine natures, as lameness to Vulcan, blindness to Cupid, and the like — to signify exuberances." 3 In keeping with this idea of Cupid is Emerson's conception of the piercing quality of love's vision, though love is usually represented as a blind god. The poem, Cupido, turns on this thought: "The solid, solid universe Is pervious to Love; With bandaged eyes he never errs, 1 The True Intellectual System of the Universe, L, 68. 2 Complete Works, II., 31-32. *lbid., III., 18. Cf. IX., 72. MYTHOLOGY 257 Around, below, above. His blinding light He flingeth white On God's and Satan's brood, And reconciles By mystic wiles The evil and the good." 1 Emerson's authority for this manner of in terpreting the defects of divine natures is Proclus. In his Commentaries on the Tim- ceus of Plato is written: "It must be care fully observed, that defects when ascribed to divine natures adumbrate transcendencies; just as those whose eyes are filled with solar light, are said to be incapable of perceiving mundane objects; for this incapacity is noth ing more than transcendency of vision. In like manner, the lameness of Vulcan sym bolically indicated his exemption from any defective progression." 2 Emerson's explana tion of the blindness of Cupid is an example contributed by himself. In Plutarch Emerson found a bit of mythology which he uses in characteristic fashion. Plutarch says: "The sun never transgresses its limited measures, as Hera- 1 Ibid., IX., 257. 2 1., 120, note i. 258 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON clitus says: if it did do so, the Furies, which are the attendants of Justice, would find it out and punish it." * This piece of mythology Emerson identifies with the doctrine of Nem esis, which he holds underlies the concep tion of compensation. "This is that ancient doctrine of Nemesis," he tells us, "who keeps watch in the universe and lets no offence go unchastised. The Furies, they said, are at tendants on justice, and if the sun in heaven should transgress his path they would punish him." 2 But no phase of ancient mythology did Emerson more carefully explain in terms of human experience than the belief in Daemons, as they are treated in the writings of Plato and the Platonists. He used details concerning them in elaborating his conception in Daemonic Love; but what is more he is care ful to state the modern equivalent of the Daemon. Thus, in a review of certain phases of demonology, he shows little regard for the significance of dreams or omens. "But the faith in peculiar and alien power," he adds, "takes another form in the modern mind, much more resembling the ancient doctrine of * Morals, III., 26. 2 Complete Works, II., 107. MYTHOLOGY 259 the guardian genius. The belief that par ticular individuals are attended by a good fortune which makes them desirable associ ates in any enterprise of uncertain success, exists not only among those who take part in political and military projects, but influences all joint action of commerce and affairs, and a corresponding assurance in the individuals so distinguished meets and justifies the expec tation of others by a boundless self-trust. . . . This faith is familiar in one form — that often a certain abdication of prudence and foresight is an element of success; that children and young persons come off safe from casualties that would have proved dan gerous to wiser people. We do not think the young will be forsaken; but he is fast ap proaching the age when the sub-miraculous external protection and leading are with drawn and he is committed to his own care. The young man takes a leap in the dark and alights safe. As he comes into manhood, he remembers passages and persons that seem, as he looks at them now, to have been super- naturally deprived of injurious influence on him. His eyes were holden that he could not see. But he learns that such risks he may no longer run. He observes, with pain, not that 260 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON he incurs mishaps here and there, but that his genius, whose invisible benevolence was tower and shield to him, is no longer present and active." 1 In another place, he explains the meaning of a presiding genius as held by the ancients by writing: "We recognize obscurely the same fact, though we give it our own names. We say that every man is entitled to be valued by his best moment. We measure our friends so. We know they have intervals of folly, whereof we take no heed, but wait these ap- pearings of the genius, which are sure and beautiful. On the other side, everybody knows people who appear bedridden, and who, with all degrees of ability, never im press us with the air of free agency. They know it, too, and peep with their eyes to see if you detect their sad plight. We fancy, could we pronounce the solving word and dis enchant them, the cloud would roll up, the little rider would be discovered and unseated, and they would regain their freedom. The remedy seems never to be far off, since the first step into thought lifts this mountain of necessity. Thought is the pent air-ball which i Complete Works, X., 15-16. MYTHOLOGY 261 can rive the planet, and the beauty which certain objects have for him is the friendly fire which expands the thought and acquaints the prisoner that liberty and power await him." 1 In such exposition of the meaning of a pre siding genius Emerson is treating in his own way a subject which Plutarch, in his Dis course Concerning Socrates' Daemon, had al ready handled and which in Proclus is the occasion for much speculation. Without adopting the views of either, Emerson main tains his independence, while at the same time engaged in a solution of the question which Socrates' utterances concerning his Daemon had raised. Thus it is evident that reading in the Platonists fed the moralizing tendency in Emerson's mind and afforded him interpreta tions of parts of ancient mythology which he either adopts as his own or with such changes as he wished to make in them. And just as he gathered homely proverbs, so he attended to the collection of such myths as attracted his attention in his reading. He found them significant expressions of the Universal Mind. i Ibid., VI., 287-288. 262 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON And thus the practice of using fables to set forth his teaching and the habit of rationaliz ing myths testify to the influence of the lit erary and critical side of Platonism on his own work. CHAPTER VII THE ASCENDENCY OF PLATONISM THE works of Plato and the Platonists were great storehouses from which Em erson drew the material of his thought on nature, soul, love, beauty, art and mythology. His indebtedness to Platonism is thus an as sured thing. But Emerson had read thought fully, if not widely, in other provinces of lit erature and philosophy, and in the course of that reading had gathered much that he worked into his essays. But no body of thought did he esteem as highly as Platonism. "Plato is philosophy," he maintained, "and philosophy is Plato." 1 Imbued with this idea, he either deliberately leavened the sug gestions that came to him through non-Pla tonic sources with the leaven of Platonism, or he openly criticized the new thought from the standpoint of Platonic theory. There thus remains the consideration of the signifi cant phases of Emerson's thinking in which 1 Complete Works, IV., 40. 263 264 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON Platonism though blended with other thought is seen in the ascendent. In the writings of Oriental peoples, espe cially the Hindoos, Emerson found much congenial reading. In his library these vol umes of the ancient East were assigned to a position on his shelves close to the Platonists ; and in his thought the teachings of both were most intimately associated ; for both dwelt on the fundamental unity of things. In his essay on Plato he uses long quotations from his Eastern books to explain the idea of the ineffable One of -the Platonists. "The rap tures of prayer and ecstasy of devotion," he explicitly states, "lose all being in one Being. This tendency finds its highest expression in the religious writings of the East, and chiefly in the Indian Scriptures, in the Vedas, the Bhagavat Geeta, and the Vishnu Purana. Those writings contain little else than this idea, and they rise to pure and sublime strains in celebrating it." 1 Emerson holds, too, that Plato drew certain elements of his thought from the East, whither, perhaps, he journeyed.2 He also maintains that the influence of the East was 1 Complete Works, IV., 49. s Ibid., 42. ASCENDENCY OF PLATONISM 265 an important factor in the development of the Neo-Platonism of Plotinus and his followers. "When Orientalism in Alexandria found the Platonists," he told the auditors in his Har vard course on philosophy, "a new school was produced. The sternness of the Greek school, feeling its way forward from argument to argument, met and combined with the beauty of Orientalism. Plotinus, Proclus, Porphyry, and Jamblicus were the apostles of the new philosophy." 1 Orientalism and Platonism were thus intimately associated in his survey of the philosophy of the ancient world. This association of the sacred writers of the East with Plato and the Platonists may have arisen from Emerson's adoption of the critical attitude of Cousin. That French philoso pher was interested both in Greek thought and in the books of the East. He maintained that the origins of Grecian culture and philos ophy are to be found in the sacred books of the Oriental peoples.2 He denominated Asia the land whose fundamental character is unity; where all the elements of human nature lay enveloped indistinct within each other; while Greece was the land in which these 1 Atlantic Monthly, LI., 826. 2 Introduction to the History of Philosophy, 42. 266 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON same elements were developed and separated.1 It is a distinction that recalls Emerson's state ment that Asia is the country of unity, while Greece is the land of culture and intellectual freedom.2 It is just this intellectual quality that pre dominates in Emerson's own adaption of the philosophy of the ancient East; wherever the teachings of the Orient enter into his thought they are intellectualized and restated in the terms of Hellenic philosophy. One doctrine of the East that attracted Emerson's attention is that of illusion. In his own work the subject is a familiar one; he has an essay and poem named Illusions and a poem, Mala, along with several scattered ref erences to the same topic. In explaining the idea he writes: "This belief that the higher use of the material world is to furnish us types or pictures to express the thoughts of the mind, is carried to its logical extreme by the Hindoos, who, following Buddha, have made it the central doctrine of their religion that what we call Nature, the external world, has no real existence, — is only phenomenal. Youth, age, property, condition, events, per- 1 Ibid., 34, 39. 2 Complete Works, IV., 52. ASCENDENCY OF PLATONISM 267 sons, — self, even, — are successive maias (de ceptions) through which Vishnu mocks and instructs the soul." 1 In Emerson illusion becomes variety and variety his favorite philosophers had taught him to connect with identity. Thus toward the end of his essay, Illusions, he writes: "The early Greek philosophers Heraclitus and Xenophanes measured their force on this problem of identity. Diogenes of Apollonia said that unless the atoms were made of one stuff, they could never blend and act with one another. But the Hindoos, in their sacred writings, express the liveliest feeling, both of the essential identity and of that illusion which they conceive variety to be." 2 Having thus identified illusions with variety, Emerson was able to resort to Platonic doctrine to explain the nature of the constant element amid all illusions. In his poem, Illusions, Emerson applies his teaching of the permanency of law in the world. Coleridge had taught him how to in terpret Plato's conception of the idea as the only constant thing in a world of perpetual flux by identifying it with the law which the 1 Complete Works, VIIL, 14-15. 2 Ibid., VI., 324. 268 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON mind finds operating in nature. Thus after a statement of the flowing of all mortal things, ever mutable and ever vanishing into vain illusions, he gives in his second stanza the as surance that — "When thou dost return On the wave's circulation, Behold the shimmer, The wild dissipation, And, out of endeavor To change and to flow, The gas becomes solid, And phantoms and nothings Return to be things, And endless imbroglio Is law and the world." 1 In a second instance he falls back on a familiar tenet of his Platonism that beneath all things there is one constant stuff. The ele ment of permanency is here conceived not as law but in a more physical way as a primal world-matter according to the old partialists among the Greek thinkers. "Such are the days," he writes, "the earth is the cup, the sky is the cover, of the immense bounty of Nature which is offered us for our daily aliment; but 1 Complete Works, IX., 287-288. ASCENDENCY OF PLATONISM 269 what a force of illusion begins life with us and attends us to the end! We are coaxed, flattered and duped from morn to eve, from birth to death ; and where is the old eye that ever saw through the deception? The Hin doos represent Maia, the illusory energy of Vishnu, as one of his principal attributes. As if, in this gale of warring elements which life is, it was necessary to bind souls to human life as mariners in a tempest lash themselves to the mast and bulwarks of a ship, and Nature employed certain illusions as her ties and straps, — a rattle, a doll, an apple, for a child; skates, a river, a boat, a horse, a gun, for the growing boy; and I will not begin to name those of the youth and adult, for they are numberless. Seldom and slowly the mask falls and the pupil is permitted to see that all is one stuff, cooked and painted under many counterfeit appearances." 1 In another mood he asserts that beneath the illusions of time is eternity and thus with Plato conceives of time as the image of eter nity. "In stripping time of its illusions, in seeking to find what is the heart of the day, we come to the quality of the moment, and drop the duration altogether. It is the 1 Complete Works, VII, 172. 270 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON depth at which we live and not at all the sur face extension that imports. We pierce to the eternity, of which time is the flitting sur face; and, really, the least acceleration of thought and the least increase of power of thought, make life to seem and to be a vast duration. We call it time ; but when that ac celeration and that deepening take effect, it acquires another and a higher name." 1 Finally, Emerson finds the stay amid the illusions of life in an experience which is reminiscent of the mystic experience of Plotinus. The most famous of Plotinus' de scriptions and the one which impressed Em erson most deeply is that closing sentence of the Select Works. "This, therefore, is the life of the Gods, and of divine and happy men, a liberation from all terrene concerns, a life unaccompanied with human pleasures, and a flight of the alone to the alone." 2 The loneliness of the experience echoes in the closing paragraph of Emerson's essay, Illu sions: "There is no chance and no anarchy in the universe. All is system and gradation. Every god is there sitting in his sphere. The young mortal enters the hall of the firmament; 1 Ibid., VII., 183. 2 p. 506. ASCENDENCY OF PLATONISM 271 there is he alone with them alone, they pour ing on him benedictions and gifts, and beckon ing him up to their thrones. On the instant, and incessantly, fall snow-storms of illusions. He fancies himself in a vast crowd which sways this way and that and whose movement and doings he must obey; he fancies him self poor, orphaned, insignificant. The mad crowd drives hither and thither, now furiously commanding this thing to be done, now that What is he that he should resist their will, and think or act for himself? Every moment new changes and new showers of deceptions to baffle and distract him. And when, by and by, for an instant, the air clears and the cloud lifts a little, there are the gods still sitting around him on their thrones, — they alone with him alone." 1 In the treatment of the Hindoo doctrine of illusions, then, Emerson comes finally to interpret it from the standpoint of those teach ings of Platonism which appear constantly throughout his work. The conception of law, or idea, the identity of all things, the doc trine of time as an image of eternity — such are the familiar tenets of his Platonism that enable him to treat the subject of illusion as 1 Complete Works, VL, 325. 272 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON the equivalent of the doctrine of the flux of things. Such a hold has Platonism upon his way of viewing the illusive character of life that he even imitates the most notable passage in Plotinus in which Plotinus teaches absolute communion of the Soul with the Divine as the highest and only reality in all experience. A second idea of the Hindoos which Emer son uses is that of the transmigration of souls. This doctrine, Emerson holds, implies the Platonic doctrine of Reminiscence. Thus he writes: "The soul having been often born, or, as the Hindoos say, 'travelling the path of existence through thousands of births,' hav ing beheld the things which are here, those which are in heaven and those which are be neath, there is nothing of which she has not gained the knowledge : no wonder that she is able to recollect, in regard to any one thing, what formerly she knew. 'For, all things in nature being linked and related, and the soul having heretofore known all, nothing hinders but that any man, who has recalled to mind, or, according to the common phrase, has learned, one thing only, should of himself re cover all his ancient knowledge, and find out again all the rest; if he have but courage, and faint not in the midst of his researches. For ASCENDENCY OF PLATONISM 273 inquiry and learning is reminiscence all.' How much more if he that inquires be a holy and god-like soul! For by being assimilated to the original soul, by whom and after whom all things subsist, the soul of man does then easily flow into all things, and all things flow into it; they mix; and he is present and sympa thetic with their structure and law." 1 This passage is characteristic of Emerson's treatment of Platonic doctrine. It is a quo tation from Plato's Meno as given in Taylor's translation, with only minor verbal changes; and the quotation includes the whole passage (excepting the inserted clause giving the Hindoo rendering) and not merely the por tion Emerson incloses in quotation marks. It also blends the doctrine of reminiscence with that of the Over-Soul which is based on the doctrine of the One as given in Plotinus. Plato thus is Neo-Platonized. And finally, it identifies the tenet of reminiscence with the Hindoo doctrine of transmigration. The conception of transmigration, then, which Emerson holds is purely a Platonic one ; it has been reinterpreted so that the purely objective rendering of the idea has given way to an in tellectual and mystical one. 1 Complete Works, IV., 96. 274 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON The first use which Emerson made of this spiritualized doctrine of transmigration is to be found in his poem, Bacchus. There he prays for wine — "Wine of wine, Blood of the world, Form of forms, and mould of statures, That I intoxicated, And by the draught assimilated, May float at pleasure through all natures; The bird-language rightly spell, And that which roses say so well." And the wine is to be a wine of reminis cence, too. "Pour, Bacchus! the remembering wine; Retrieve the loss of me and mine ! Vine for vine be antidote, And the grape requite the lote ! Haste to cure the old despair — Reason in Nature's lotus drenched, The memory of ages quenched; Give them again to shine ; Let wine repair what this undid; And where the infection slid, A dazzling memory revive; Refresh the faded tints, Recut the aged prints, And write my old adventures with the pen ASCENDENCY OF PLATONISM 275 Which on the first day drew, Upon the tablets blue, The dancing Pleiads and eternal men." 1 Other traces of Platonic influence appear in the poem. Plotinus holds to the contem plative activity of all things, even inanimate and Emerson reflects the same idea when he prays for wine — "That I, drinking this, Shall hear far Chaos talk with me; Kings unborn shall walk with me; And the poor grass shall plot and plan What it will do when it is man." 2 In the title of the poem Platonism appears. Hafiz had used wine as a theme for verse but its symbolic use in Emerson is purely Platonic. "Bacchus," explains Proclus "is the mundane intellect from which the soul and the body of the world are suspended. . . . But the theologists frequently call Bacchus wine, from the last of his gifts. . . ." 3 The wine that the poet prays for thus becomes the in tellect which in its divine intoxication is to 1 Complete Works, IX., 125-127. 2 Ibid., IX., 126. 3 On the Theology of Plato, I., 216-217. 276 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON float through all beings. And this intoxica tion is only the inspiration that the true poet should have. Hence it was natural that Emerson in his own copy of the Poems should write as a motto for his poem this sentence on poetic madness freely rendered from Plato's Phaedrus: "The man who is his own master knocks in vain at the doors of poetry." l It is quite evident, then, that the transmigration of soul in Emerson is not the physical kind the Hindoos taught but a more spiritual experi ence as conceived by Plato and the Platonists. Even when Emerson does treat transmigra tion as an objective thing, he interprets its meaning as Cudworth, the Cambridge Plato- nist, had suggested. In his copy of Cud- worth a marked passage reads: "But as for that other transmigration of human souls into the bodies of brutes, though it cannot be de nied but that many of the ancients admitted it also, yet Timgeus Locrus, and divers others of the Pythagoreans, rejected it, any otherwise than as it might be taken for an allegorical de scription of the beastly transformation that is made of men's souls by vice." 2 In the same manner Emerson writes: "The transmigra- 1 Bohn translation, I., 321. Cf. Complete Works IX., 443. 2 The True Intellectual System of the Universe, I., 70. ASCENDENCY OF PLATONISM 277 tion of souls is no fable. I would it were ; but men and women are only half human. Every animal of the barn yard, the field and the for est, of the earth and of the waters that are under the earth, has contrived to get a foot ing and to leave the print of its features and form in some one or other of these upright, heaven-facing speakers. Ah! brother, stop the ebb of thy soul, — ebbing downward into the forms into whose habits thou hast now for many years slid." 1 In certain other points of indebtedness to the Hindoo philosophy the persistency of Platonism is still noticeable. The name Over- Soul may well have come from the Bhagavat- Gita, as one critic has pointed out.2 There the Supreme Spirit is called Adhyatma (Adhi meaning above, superior to, or presiding over; and atma, the soul, — not the soul that presides over all, but that which is above the soul it self) . But the meaning which Emerson gives to the expression in his essay, The Over-Soul is, as already shown, that which Platonism had taught him concerning the One and its relation to the other hypostases. A Hindoo term has 1 Complete Works, II., 32. 2 W. T. Harris, Emerson's Orientalism, in Genius and Character of Emerson, edited by F. B. Sanborn. 278 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON thus been filled with Greek thought; or Greek thought has been capped with an Hindoo name. In Emerson's poem, Brahma, is found an ex pression of Emerson's doctrine of soul, or God, which is almost entirely Hindoo in its man ner of speech.1 Without a knowledge of the Bhagavat-Gita the poem could never have as sumed the form it now has. But its doctrines of the soul — immortality and independence of time and space, to which it gives expression. are shared by the Platonist as well as the Hin doo. And the sentiment of the third stanza — "They reckon ill who leave me out; When me they fly, I am the wings ; I am the doubter and the doubt, And I the hymn the Brahmin sings — " 2 is that teaching familiar in Greek philosophy from Parmenides through Plato to the Neo- Platonists; namely, that the knower and the thing known are one; or, as the poem says — "I am the doubter and the doubt." Emerson had used the same idea in his conception of the Over-Soul and recognized its importance 2 Complete Works, IX., 195. ASCENDENCY OF PLATONISM 279 in a history of the intellect. It thus was a nat ural sentiment to use in a song of the soul such as Brahma is. And so it is plain that in the fusion of Hin doo teaching with Platonism the latter re tains its own form and is often felt as an influ ence transforming the Hindoo philosophy into a new product. At times the language is that of the ancient East but it veils Greek thought When the influence of Emerson's Oriental readings comes to be worked out in all its de tails, it may be shown that they colored the manner of his speech and accentuated the con trast between body and spirit, but the underly ing intellectualism of Emerson's mind will still claim a nearer kinship with Plato and the Platonists than with the writings of the Hin doos. The doctrines of Christianity are a second body of thought which Emerson associates with Platonism. "Read in Plato," he says, "and you shall find Christian dogmas, and not only so, but stumble on our evangelical phrases." 1 "Galvanism," he asserts, "is in his Phaedo: Christianity is in it."2 It is natural, then, to examine certain phases of Christian 1 Ibid., VIII, 180. 2 Ibid., IV., 40. 280 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON teaching in order to determine to what extent Emerson has interpreted them according to the doctrines of Platonism. Sin in Emerson is viewed in its relation to intellect rather than to conscience as Christian practice views it. "There is no crime to the intellect. That is antinomian or hyper- nomian, and judges law as well as fact. 'It is worse than a crime, it is a blunder,' said Napoleon, speaking the language of the intel lect. To it, the world is a problem in math ematics or the science of quantity and it leaves out praise and blame and all weak emotions. All stealing is comparative. If you come to absolutes, pray who does not steal? Saints are sad, because they behold sin (even when they speculate) from the point of view of the conscience, and not of the intellect; a confu sion of thought. Sin, seen from the thought, is diminution, or less; seen from the conscience or will, it is pravity or bad. The intellect names it shade, absence of light, and no es sence. The conscience must feel it as essence, essential evil. This it is not; it has an objec tive existence, but no subjective." Such reasoning shows that Emerson identi fies sin with evil, as conceived by the Plato- 1 Ibid., III., 79. ASCENDENCY OF PLATONISM 281 who held that it was non-being. As Proclus in his treatise on the Subsistence of Evil says, "There is not, however, such a thing as unmingled evil, and evil itself, or an eternal idea, form and essence of evil, but moral evil is mixed with good, and so far as it is good, it subsists from divinity, but so far as evil, it is derived from another cause which is impotent. For evil is nothing else than a greater or less declination, departure, defect and privation from the good itself, and which is good alone, in the same manner as darkness from the sun." Emerson adopts the theory that men do evil involuntarily. "I believe not in two classes of men, but in man in two moods, in Philip drunk and Philip sober. I think according to the good-hearted word of Plato, 'Unwillingly the soul is deprived of truth.' Iron conserv ative, miser, or thief, no man is but by a sup posed necessity which he tolerates by shortness or torpidity of sight." 2 This idea is Plato's familiar doctrine. "No one," he holds, in the Timceus, "is vol untarily bad; but he who is depraved be comes so through a certain bad habit of body 1 On the Theology of Plato, II., 500. 2 Complete Works, III., 271. 282 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON and an ill-governed education; and to every one these are inimical, as they result in a cer tain evil." 1 The subject of prayer is one which Emer son noted in the Platonists ; in his Proclus and his lamblichus he has indexed the most sig nificant passages on this topic. There he found prayer in its highest form identified with the mystic union of soul with the divine. "The third and most perfect species of prayer," lamblichus explains, "is the seal of ineffable union 'with the divinities, in whom it establishes all the power and authority of prayer; and thus causes the soul to repose in the Gods, as in a never failing port . . . It also gradually and silently draws upwards the manners of our soul, by divesting them of every thing foreign to a divine nature, and clothes us with the perfections of the Gods. Besides this, it produces an indissoluble communion and friendship with divinity, nourishes a divine love, and inflames the divine part of the soul. Whatever is of an opposing and contrary nature in the soul, it expiates and purifies; expels whatever is prone to generation, and retains anything of the dregs of mortality in its ethereal and 1 Bohn translation, II., 402. ASCENDENCY OF PLATONISM 283 splendid spirit, perfects a good hope and faith concerning the reception of divine light; and, in one word, renders those by whom it is employed the familiars and domestics of the Gods." 1 This conception of prayer as a union with God is at the basis of Emerson's belief that a greater self-reliance must characterize our prayers. The source of the reliance is, as has already been indicated, in the dwelling of God or the One in the soul of man. There fore he writes: "In what prayers do men allow themselves! That which they call a holy office is not so much as brave and manly. Prayer looks abroad and asks for some foreign addition to come through some foreign vir tue, and loses itself in endless mazes of natural and supernatural, and mediatorial and mirac ulous. Prayer that craves a particular com modity, anything less than all good, is vicious. Player is the contemplation of the facts of life from the highest point of view. It is the so liloquy of a beholding and jubilant soul. It is the spirit of God pronouncing his works good. But prayer as a means to effect a private end is meanness and theft. It sup poses dualism and not unity in nature and 1 On the Mysteries, 271-273. 284 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON consciousness. As soon as man is at one with God, he will not beg." l In his conception of the fall of man Emer son adopts the Platonic explanation. "It is very unhappy, but too late to be helped, the discovery we have made that we exist. That discovery is called the Fall of Man. Ever afterwards we suspect our instruments. We have learned that we do not see directly, but mediately, and that we have no means of cor recting these colored and distorting lenses which we are, or of computing the amount of their errors. Perhaps these subject-lenses have a creative power; perhaps there are no objects. Once we lived in what we saw ; now, the rapaciousness of this new power, which threatens to absorb all things, engages us. Nature, art, persons, letters, religions, objects, successively tumble in, and God is but one of its ideas." 2 This explanation which finds the fall of man to be a deterioration in his faculty of spiritual intuition is in keeping with the theory of the descent of the soul which Pro- clus gives in a passage marked by Emerson. 1 Complete Works, II., 77. *Ibid., Ill, 75-76. ASCENDENCY OF PLATONISM 285 "From the beginning, therefore, and at first, the soul was united to the Gods, and its unity to their one. But afterwards the Soul de parting from this divine union descended into intellect, and no longer possessed real beings unitedly, and in one, but apprehended and sur veyed them by simple projections, and, as it were, contacts of its intellect. In the next place, departing from intellect, and descend ing into reasoning and dianoia, it no longer ap prehended real beings by simple intuitions, but syllogistically and transitively, proceeding from one thing to another, from propositions to conclusions. Afterwards, abandoning true reasoning, and the dissolving peculiarity, it descended into generation, and became filled with much irrationality and perturbation." 1 Associated with the idea of the fall of man is Emerson's teaching of imbecility as the pre vailing trait of man through all the ages. "The key to the age may be this, or that, or the other, as the young orators describe; the key to all ages is — Imbecility; imbecility in the vast majority of men at all times, and even in heroes in all but certain eminent moments ; victims of gravity, custom and fear. This 1 Quoted in lamblichus, On the Mysteries, 355. 286 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON gives force to the strong — that the multitude have no habit of self-reliance or original action." l This is the teaching of lamblichus. In a passage marked by Emerson he says: "For since it is not possible to speak rightly about the Gods without the Gods, much less can any one perform works which are of an equal dig nity with divinity, and obtain the fore-knowl edge of everything without [the inspiring in fluence of] the Gods. For the human race is imbecile, and of small estimation, sees but a lit tle and possesses a connascent nothingness ; and the only remedy of its inherent error, pertur bation, and unstable mutation, is its participa tion, as much as possible, of a certain portion of divine light." 2 In reviewing Emerson's treatment of the doctrines of sin, evil, prayer, the fall of man, his weakness, all of which bulk so prominently in Christian dogmatics, it appears that the in- tellectualism of Plato and the mysticism of the Platonists determine Emerson's interpreta tion. Sin and evil are not positive things; they are viewed from the intellect as merely negative. The essence of prayer is the mystic 1 Complete Works, VI., 54. 2 On the Mysteries, 164. ASCENDENCY OF PLATONISM 287 union of the soul with the divine which prac tically excludes the possibility of such simple requests as "Give us this day our daily bread." The fall of man is a lapse of intellect which begins when man ceases to live mystically united with the Divine. The intellectual quality of all this teaching attracted Emerson. The lack of this he felt in Christian teaching; that appealed to emotion rather than to intellect in man. The Platonists dwelt "in a worship which makes the sanctities of Chris tianity look parvenues and popular; for 'per suasion is in soul, but necessity is in intel lect.' " 1 In that distinction, which Emerson found in Plotinus,2 Emerson reveals the differ ence he felt between Christian and Platonic teaching. Hence results the purely intellec tual character of all he has to say on Chris tian subjects. The ascendency of Platonism in Emerson's thinking appears in his relation to the tran scendental philosophy of Germany. He came in contact with this thought in his reading in Coleridge. The Biographta Literaria and The Friend of Coleridge are two works which Emerson had carefully studied, and in them 1 Complete Works, II., 346. 2 Select Works, 417. 288 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON the teachings of Kant and especially of Schell- ing are openly stated to have been important factors in the development of Coleridge's spiritual life. Emerson gained a further knowledge of German philosophy from an anonymous translation of The Critique of Pure Reason, published in 1838. This book is in his library and shows some markings and an index with entries — uLocke and Hume," "Immortality," and "Oblate Sphericity." Emerson was familiar also with an account of the systems of Kant, Fichte, and Schelling that appeared in the Christian Examiner for March, 1833. He valued highly Dr. James Hutchinson Stirling's Secret of Hegel; but as this book was not published until 1865 ^ could have influenced Emerson's thinking only after his main work had been done. The same is true even in a greater degree of his indebted ness to Edward Caird's A Critical Account of the Philosophy of Kant (1877), which is also in his library. As far then as his opportuni ties were concerned Emerson was able even in his early period of literary activity to gain a notion of Kant's philosophy directly through translation and of the teachings of Schelling and the others through indirect sources. But Emerson does not forget the primacy of ASCENDENCY OF PLATONISM 289 Platonism in his criticism of this German philosophy. He does not regard it as an orig inal thought product: he finds its sources in the older philosophies of Greece. "Any his tory of philosophy fortifies my faith," he says, "by showing me that what high dogmas I had supposed were the rare and late fruit of a cumulative culture, and only now possible to some recent Kant or Fichte — were the prompt improvisations of the earliest inquir ers; of Parmenides, Heraclitus, and Xeno- phanes." 1 "Hegel," he adds in another place, "pre-exists in Proclus, and long before, in Heraclitus and Parmenides." 2 Schell- ing's identity-philosophy couched in the statement that "all difference is quantitative," he includes among those generalizations which "do all have a kind of filial retrospect to Plato and the Greeks."3 Of Coleridge Emerson once speaks very highly as one "whose philosophy compares with others much as astronomy with other sciences ; taking post at the center, and, as from a specular mount, sending sovereign glances to the cir cumference of things." 4 This was said when 1 Complete Works, L, 160. 2 Ibid., VIII., 180. 3 Ibid., V., 241, 242. 4 J. E. Cabot, A Memoir of Ralph Waldo Emerson, I., 161. 290 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON Emerson was but twenty-three years old; but later, when he came to review the teachings of Plato, he found Coleridge a "reader of Plato, translating into the vernacular, wittily, his good things." 1 Such relegation of Coleridge and the Ger mans to a dependency upon ancient Greek thought does not mean that Emerson totally ignored their work. His writings bear traces of indebtedness to German transcendentalism ; but in his treatment of German thought he does not identify himself very closely with the Germans. He was content to accept the terms they used and at times he agrees with their doctrines; but true to his favorite Plato- nism, he always reads its meanings into these terms and consciously interprets the doctrines of the Germans in his own characteristically Platonic manner. Emerson's conception of the transcenden- talist will bear out this statement. He de votes an entire lecture to this subject. If there had been much of the German product in his mind it would surely have come to the surface. But his point of view is that of one who considers the question from a superior height. Transcendentalism is no new thing 1 Complete Works, IV., 39. ASCENDENCY OF PLATONISM 291 to him. "The first thing we have to say re specting what are called new views here in New England, at the present time, is, that they are not new, but the very oldest thoughts cast into the mould of these new times . . . What is popularly called Transcendentalism among us is Idealism; Idealism as it appears in I842."1 His characterization of the Transcenden- talist thus proceeds to enumerate traits which have already been seen to root themselves in Platonism. At the very heart of the philoso phy of the Transcendentalist is the emanation Theory. "His experience," Emerson says, "in clines him to behold the procession of facts you call the world, as flowing perpetually outward from an invisible, unsounded centre in him self, centre alike of him and them, and neces sitating him to regard all things as having a subjective or relative existence, relative to that aforesaid Unknown Centre of him." 2 Out of this doctrine arises the central idea of his ethics — self-reliance.3 The Transcendental ist believes, too, "in miracle, in the perpetual openness of the human mind to a new influx 1 Complete Works, L, 329. */&«., L, 334. a Ibid. 292 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON of light and power; he believes in inspiration and in ecstasy." 1 The Transcendentalists are lonely people caring little for society and at times unwilling to take an active part in its labors. But such seclusion is for the purpose of enabling them the better to keep in touch with the divine within themselves.2 They are lovers of beauty, too. "In the eternal trinity of Truth, Goodness, and Beauty, each in its perfection including the three, they prefer to make Beauty the sign and head." 3 All these traits recall the characteristic teach ings of Emerson which, as already pointed out, were molded after the manner of the Platonists. In fact the only connection with Kant that Emerson speaks of is through the name. He thus declares: "It is well known to most of my audience that the Idealism of the present day acquired the name Transcenden tal from the use of that term by Immanuel Kant, of Konigsburg, who replied to the skep tical philosophy of Locke, which insisted that there was nothing in the intellect which was not previously in the experience of the senses, by showing that there was a very important 1 Ibid., 335. 2 Ibid., 342-354- 3 Ibid., 354- ASCENDENCY OF PLATONISM 293 class of ideas or imperative forms, which did not come by experience, but through which experience was acquired; that there were in tuitions of the mind itself; and he denom inated them Transcendental forms. The ex traordinary profoundness and precision of that man's thinking has given vogue to his nomenclature, in Europe and America, to that extent that whatever belongs to the class of intuitive thought is popularly called at the present day Transcendental." * Far from claiming that this name was given because of any conscious connection with the philosophy of Kant on the part of those who were called Transcendentalists, he openly states in another account that the name was given, nobody knows by whom.2 And he adds that the only bond of union between the mem bers in the group of New England Transcen dentalists was that "perhaps they only agreed in having fallen upon Coleridge and Words worth and Goethe; then on Carlyle, with pleasure and sympathy." 3 But the ascendency of Platonism is appar ent not only in Emerson's conception of the 1 Complete Works, I., 339-340. --Ibid., X., 343. *lbid., 342. 294 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON transcendental movement in New England but even in his manner of interpreting the doctrines of the German philosophers. This is borne out by the meaning which Emerson attaches to intuition. Emerson himself recognizes a difference between Kant's conception of intuition and that interpretation which was generally main tained among the New England Transcen- dentalists. As the quotation on the origin of the name shows, Emerson sees a difference be tween the transcendental forms through which according to Kant experience was ac quired, and simple intuitive thought. Kant has reference to the intuitions of form and space through which our knowledge of the ex ternal world is given; but Emerson means by intuitive thought, at least in its most impor tant form, nothing less than the mystic ex perience through which the soul of man en ters into divine union with God. Thus he explains that when we inquire into the nature of the aboriginal self, on which a universal reliance may be grounded, the inquiry leads us to that primary wisdom which he calls in tuition as distinguished from tuition.1 This is not a mere form of knowledge, of which we 1 Complete Works, II., 64. ASCENDENCY OF PLATONISM 295 become aware only by a process of reasoning on a priori grounds; but it is a conscious ex perience of the soul which is higher than knowledge. It is thus a different thing from Kant's intuition. So too with Emerson's use of the terms Rea son and Understanding. Of these he writes to his brother: "Now that I have used the words, let me ask you, Do you draw the dis tinction of Milton, Coleridge, and the Ger mans between Reason and Understanding? I think it a philosophy itself, and like all truth, very practical. Reason is the highest faculty of the soul, what we mean often by the soul it self ; it never reasons, never proves; it simply perceives, it is vision. The Understanding toils all the time, compares, contrives, adds, argues ; near-sighted but strong-sighted, dwell ing in the present, the expedient, the custom ary." 1 As this quotation shows the distinction ante dates Kant and is found by Emerson in the seventeenth century writers; in Milton, for instance, in whom Platonism is the ruling philosophy, as indeed it was in the best minds of his time. The writings of Kant had given vogue to these terms Reason, Understanding, 1 J. E. Cabot, A Memoir of Ralph Waldo Emerson, I., 218. 296 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON Intuition; but as they appear in Emerson they are used in a sense which is purely in keeping with his Platonism. It is to be observed, too, that Emerson is following Coleridge's lead in thus interpret ing these terms. Coleridge tells us that he had "cautiously discriminated the terms, the reason and the understanding, encouraged and confirmed by the authority of our genuine divines and philosophers, before the Revolu tion." 1 He quotes a passage from Milton to support his statement, a passage which Emer son had in mind also. And he explicitly states that the use of the word intuition by these divines and philosophers is more in clusive than Kant's. "I take this occasion to observe," he writes, "that here and elsewhere Kant uses the terms intuition, and the verb active (intueri Germanice anschauen) for which we have unfortunately no correspon dent word, exclusively for that which can be represented in space and time. He therefore consistently and rightly denies the possibility of intellectual intuitions. But as I see no ade quate reason for this exclusive sense of the term, I have reverted to its wider significa- 1 The Complete Works of Samuel Taylor Coleridge, III., ASCENDENCY OF PLATONISM 297 tion, authorized by our elder theologians and metaphysicians, according to whom the term comprehends all truths known to us without a medium." 1 This use of the term is associated with the practice of the Platonists which was followed by the seventeenth century theologians that Coleridge refers to. And it is interesting to note that Coleridge falls back upon Plotinus for an explanation of such intuitive knowl edge. Thus to illustrate the character of the transcendental consciousness he quotes Plo tinus: "It is not lawful to inquire from whence it sprang, as if it were a thing subject to place and motion, for it neither approached hither, nor again departs from hence to some other place; but it either appears to us or it does not appear. So that we ought not to pur sue it with a view of detecting its secret source, but to watch in quiet till it suddenly shines upon us; preparing ourselves for the blessed spectacle as the eye waits patiently for the rising sun." 2 Intuition thus blends in Coleridge with the mystic vision as taught in Plotinus. Direct evidence to prove Emerson's con- 352, note. *Ibid., III., 327-328. 298 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON nection with Coleridge is at hand. To the doctrine of correlation of mind and matter Emerson was an enthusiastic adherent; and the perception of the relation between these two poles of thought, mind and matter, he de scribes as an intuition. Thus he writes: "This relation between the mind and matter is not fancied by some poet, but stands in the will of God, and so is free to be known by all men. It appears to men, or it does not ap pear. When in fortunate hours we ponder this miracle, the wise man doubts if at all other times he is not blind and deaf, . . . for the universe becomes transparent, and the light of higher laws than its own shines through it." 1 The connection of this idea with Plotinus' explanation of intuition is seen in the identity of expressions. Plotinus writes of the mystic experience — "It either appears to us or it does not appear"; and Emerson echoes the lan guage in his — "It appears to men, or it does not appear." Now, this translation of the passage of Plotinus in question appears only in Coleridge's account; it is not to be found in any of Thomas Taylor's renderings. Emerson must then have noted it in Coleridge. i Complete Works, I., 33-34. ASCENDENCY OF PLATONISM 299 It explained intuition in a manner more con genial to his way of thinking than was Kant's restricted use of the term. Intuition thus be came identical with the mystic experience he dwells upon in his Over-Soul. The ascendency of Platonism is also present in Emerson's treatment of Kant's conception of morals. On the primacy of morals Kant lays great stress. A will is morally good, he holds, when it is determined solely by duty. And this duty is felt in a moral consciousness which expresses itself in the form of a de mand, or a categorical imperative: Thou shalt do what the law prescribes, uncondition ally, whatever consequences may result.1 When Emerson adopts this high conception of duty, he connects the experience with the mystic union of man with the Supreme Wis dom. The perception of the moral law, he holds is "divine and deifying. It is the beati tude of man. It makes him illimitable. Through it, the soul first knows itself. It corrects the capital mistake of the infant man, who seeks to be great by following the great, and hopes to derive advantages from another — by showing the fountain of all good to be in himself, and that he, equally with every 1 Friedrich Paulsen, Immanuel Kant, 305. 300 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON man, is an inlet into the deeps of Reason. When he says, 'I ought'; when love warms him ; when he chooses, warned from on high, the good and great deed ; then, deep melodies wander through his soul from Supreme Wis dom." 1 Out of Kant's conception of the categorical imperative comes universality as the test of all morally right conduct. The law thus be comes: Act so that thy maxim may be cap able of becoming the universal natural law of all rational beings. Or as Emerson says: "He is moral — we say it with Marcus Aurelius and with Kant — whose aim or motive may become a universal rule, binding on all intel ligent beings." 2 But Emerson goes on to deduce from this definition a new conception of Universal Mind. "If from these external statements," he continues after applying the rule to justice, courage, love and humility, "we come a little nearer to the fact, our first experiences in moral, as in intellectual nature, force us to discriminate a universal mind, identical in all men. Certain biases, talents, executive skills, are special to each individual; but the high, 1 Complete Works, L, 125. rf., X., 92. ASCENDENCY OF PLATONISM 301 contemplative, all-commanding vision, the sense of Right and Wrong, is alike in all. Its attributes are self-existence, eternity, intuition and command. It is the mind of the mind. We belong to it, not it to us. It is in all men, and constitutes them men. In bad men it is dormant, as health is in men entranced or drunken; but, however inoperative, it exists underneath whatever vices and errors. The extreme simplicity of this intuition embar rasses every attempt at analysis. We can only mark, one by one, the perfections which it combines in every act. It admits of no ap peal, looks to no superior essence. It is the reason of things." 1 Kant's conception of morals, then, led Emerson to restate his doctrine of Universal Mind. To that, he held firm; it is central in his beliefs. But the insight which Kant gave him into the true nature of moral conduct so impressed his mind that he was led to state his favorite doctrine in a form that would make it hold for morals as well as for the intellect. This he was ready to do because in his study of Plato he had come to realize that intellect in him is always moral. Another instance of Emerson's interpreta- 1 Complete Works, X., 93. 302 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON tion of a teaching of German Transcendental ism is found in his treatment of Jacobi's idea that man is superior to law. Such an idea, Emerson maintains is held by the Transcen- dentalist. "In action he easily incurs the charge of anti-nomianism by his avowal that he, who has the Law-giver, may with safety not only neglect, but even contravene every written commandment In the play of Othello, the expiring Desdemona absolves her husband of the murder, to her attendant Emilia. Afterwards, when Emilia charges him with the crime, Othello exclaims, "You heard her say herself it was not I." Emilia replies, "The more angel she, and thou the blacker devil." "Of this fine incident, Jacobi, the Tran scendental moralist, makes use, with other parallel instances, in his reply to Fichte. Jacobi, refusing all measure of right and wrong except the determinations of the private spirit, remarks that there is no crime but has sometimes been a virtue. 'I,' he says, 'I am that atheist, that godless person who, in op position to an imaginary doctrine of calcula- ASCENDENCY OF PLATONISM 303 tion, would lie as the dying Desdemona lied; would lie and deceive, as Pylades when he personated Orestes; would assassinate like Timoleon; would perjure myself like Epami- nondas and John de Witt; I would resolve on suicide like Cato; I would commit sacri lege with David; yea, and pluck ears of corn on the Sabbath, for no other reason than that I was fainting for lack of food. For I have assurance in myself that in pardoning these faults according to the letter, man exerts the sovereign right which the majesty of his be ing confers on him; he sets the seal of his divine nature to the grace he accords.' " 1 This account of Jacobi's belief comes from Coleridge, who gives a translation of Jacobi's letter to Fichte: "Yes, I am that atheist, that godless person, who in opposition to an imagi nary doctrine of calculation, to a mere ideal fabric of general consequences that can never be realized, would lie, as the dying Desde mona lied; lie and deceive as Pylades when he personated Orestes; would commit sacri lege with David; yea and pluck ears of corn on the Sabbath, for no other reason than that I was fainting from lack of food, and that the law was made for man, and not man for the 1 Complete Works, I., 336-337. 304 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON law." 1 In a footnote Coleridge gives the quotation from Othello that Jacobi refers to. A comparison of these two passages shows the character of Emerson's additions to Jacobi's statement. The four extra historical instances which Emerson adds to Jacobi's list do not change his rendering materially; but the final sentence of Emerson's account con tains a significant addition to Jacobi's words. It gives a justification of Jacobi's belief — a justification based upon a purely Platonic no tion of the divine nature of man. In adding the sentence giving this new thought Emerson had in mind a passage in his Select Works of Plotinus. Plotinus is writing of the union of the soul with the One, which means that the soul becomes God. To the passage Taylor appends a note which Emer son marked in his own copy and which he elsewhere makes use of.2 The note reads: "Hence Aristotle in his Politics also says, that he who surpasses beyond all comparison the rest of his fellow citizens in virtue, ought to be considered as a God among men. He also observes, that such a one is no longer a 1 The Complete Works of Samuel Taylor Coleridge, II., 285. 2 Complete Works, X., 477. ASCENDENCY OF PLATONISM 305 part of the city, that law is not for him, since he is a law to himself, and that it would be ridiculous in anyone to subject him to the laws. Let no one, however, who is not thus transcendently virtuous, fancy that law also is not for him . . . Observe, too, that when Plotinus calls the man who is able in this life to see divinity a God, he means that he is a god only according to similitude; for in this way, men transcendently wise and good are called by Plato, Gods and divine." * The philosophy of Kant and the Germans, then, cannot be considered as the main source of Emerson's transcendentalism. He found his inspiration in a scheme of thought that antedated the appearance of the Germans by over two thousand years. He does use the terms common in that later phase of specula tion. They were in the air at the time and he does not hesitate to appropriate them. But he gives them a new meaning. Such truths, too, in their scheme of morals as appealed to him he avails himself of; but the interpreta tion he subjects them to bespeaks the ascen dency of Platonism in his way of thinking. His indebtedness to the Germans is thus a trifling matter and what is more his use of 1 Select Works, 500, note i. 306 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON their suggestions cannot be adequately ex plained unless the influence of Platonism upon them is reckoned with. It is true, that Kant and Schelling affected Coleridge's thought. Without a knowledge of Kant's reasoning concerning the intuitions of time and space Coleridge would never have come to conceive of law as an idea which appears in mind and at the same time is pres ent in nature. And had this correlation of law and idea not appeared in Coleridge it would have kept Emerson from interpreting one phase of Plato as he did. But the inves tigation of Coleridge's indebtedness to the Germans falls without the scope of the pres ent inquiry; it is sufficient to acknowledge it. The ascendency of Platonism in Emerson shows itself also in the formal criticism to which he subjects the teachings of those men in whom he has been interested. In his Rep resentative Men he has left his appreciation of Swedenborg, Montaigne, Shakespeare, Goethe; but the defect of each is uniform; he did not measure up to that ideal which Emer son had fashioned in accordance with Plato nism. In Swedenborg Emerson was acquainted with a mind that had fed upon Platonism and ASCENDENCY OF PLATONISM 307 out of it had built up its theory of symbolism. This theory was known to Plato, Emerson points out, "as is evident from his twice bi sected line in the sixth book of the Repub lic." 1 But Swedenborg, he goes on to add "first put the fact into a detached and scien tific statement, because it was habitually pres ent to him, and never not seen." 2 Emerson is not, however, blind to the faults of Sweden- borg's use of this theory. In working out the theory in his doctrine of the correspondences between thoughts and things, his design, Emerson holds "was narrowed and defeated by the exclusively theologic direction which his inquiries took. His perception of nature is not human and universal, but is mystical and Hebraic. He fastens each natural ob ject to a theologic notion — a horse signifies carnal understanding; a tree, perception; the moon, faith; a cat means this; an ostrich that; an artichoke this other — and poorly tethers every symbol to a several ecclesiastic sense. The slippery Proteus is not so easily caught. In nature, each individual symbol plays in numerable parts, as each particle of matter circulates in turn through every system. The 1 Complete Works, IV., 116-117. 2 /&«*., 117. 308 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON central identity enables any one symbol to ex press successively all the qualities and shades of real being." 1 In other words Sweden- borg's symbolism is not developed on the ab stract and universal lines that Emerson had been led by the Platonists to follow. In his treatment of Shakespeare he applies his notion of the poet as philosopher and finds his Shakespeare wanting. As the ideal poet should do, Shakespeare "knew that a tree had another use than for apples, and corn another than for meal, and the ball of the earth, than for tillage and roads; that these things bore a second and finer harvest to the mind, being emblems of its thoughts, and conveying in all their natural history a certain mute commen tary on human life. Shakspeare employed them as colors to compose his picture. He rested in their beauty; and never took the step which seemed inevitable to such genius, namely to explore the virtue which resides in these symbols and imparts this power: — what is that which they themselves say?" 2 In other words Shakespeare does not agree with the ideal of the poet which Emerson had de veloped out of his Platonic sources. 1 Complete Works, IV., 120-121. 2 Ibid., 216-217. ASCENDENCY OF PLATONISM 309 Montaigne was a writer who cast a spell over Emerson. Speaking of his work Emer son says: "It seemed to me as if I had my self written the book, in some former life, so sincerely it spoke to my thought and experi ence." 1 Yet for the scepticism for which Montaigne stands Emerson had no sympathy. "The final solution in which skepticism is lost," he writes, "is in the moral sentiment, which never forfeits its supremacy. All moods may be safely tried, and their weight allowed to all objections; the moral senti ment as easily outweighs them all, as any one. This is the drop which balances the sea. I play with the miscellany of facts, and take those superficial views which we call skepti cism; but I know that they will presently ap pear to me in that order which makes skepti cism impossible. A man of thought must feel the thought that is parent of the universe; that the masses of nature do undulate and flow. . . .2 Let a man learn to look for the permanent in the mutable and fleeting; let him learn to bear the disappearance of things he was wont to reverence without losing his reverence; let him learn that he is here, not rf., 162. 183. 310 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON to work but to be worked upon; and that, though abyss open under abyss, and opinion displace opinion, all are at last contained in the Eternal Cause . . ." 1 Skepticism in Emerson thus loses itself in mysticism as he had been taught by Plotinus to conceive it. Of Goethe Emerson speaks at times in high praise; but his great reservation finds Goethe wanting in that high power of philosophic analysis which contents itself with nothing less than absolute unity. "I dare not say," he writes, "that Goethe ascended to the highest grounds from which genius has spoken. He has not worshipped the highest unity; he is incapable of a self-surrender to the moral sentiment . . . He has no aims less large than the conquest of universal nature, of uni versal truth, to be his portion . . . That is, Goethe fails to satisfy that unifying tendency of Emerson's mind which enabled him to appreciate the doctrine of the One as expounded in Plotinus and the Platonists. It is evident that Emerson read as a Plato- nist. Swedenborg, Shakespeare, Montaigne, and Goethe, are all held up to the ideals of Platonism and their deficiencies revealed by a 1 Ibid., 186. *Ibid., 284. ASCENDENCY OF PLATONISM 311 comparison of their ideas with Emerson's con ception of Platonism. He applies the same standard of judgment to the body of English literature with which he was most familiar. In his review of the literature of England he divides its writers into Platonists, or those that elect to see identity in things, and non- Platonists, or those that chose to see dis crepancies. Thus More, Hooker, Bacon, Sidney, Lord Brooke, Herbert, Browne, Donne, Spenser, Chapman, Milton, Crashaw, Norris, Cudworth, Berkeley, Jeremy Taylor are Platonists.1 Bacon, he holds, has traits of both classes; but it is significant that Emerson dwells upon the ideal, or Platonic, element in his work. Thus he extracts from Bacon's Advancement of Learning2 an account of Bacon's prima philosophia, which, as has been seen, was a factor in developing Emerson's conception of the correlation of mind and matter. "Bacon, capable of ideas, yet devoted to ends," says Emerson, "required in his map of the mind, first of all, universality, or prima philosophia; the receptacle for all such profitable observa- 1 Complete Works, V., 238. 2 Works of Francis Bacon, edited by Basil Montagu, II., 48, 93, 126, 128, 176. 312 THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON tions and axioms as fall not within the com pass of any of the special parts of the philosophy, but are more common and of a higher stage. He held this element essen tial; it is never out of mind; he never spares rebukes for such as neglect it; believing that no perfect discovery can be made in a flat or level, but you must ascend to a higher science. 'If any man thinketh philosophy and univer sality to be idle studies, he doth not consider that all professions are from thence served and supplied; and this I take to be a great cause that has hindered the progression of learning, because these fundamental knowl edges have been studied but in passage.' He explained himself by giving various quaint examples of the summary or common laws of which each science has its own illustration. He complains that 'he finds this part of learn ing very deficient, the profounder sort of wits drawing a bucket now and then for their own use, but the spring-head unvisited. This was the dry light which did scorch and offend most men's watery natures.' " 1 But the most significant thing in Emerson's account is the identification of this aim of Bacon's with that expressed in Plato's con- 1 Complete Works, V., 240-241. ASCENDENCY OF PLATONISM 313 ception of the metaphysical basis of all art. Thus Emerson adds to his account of Bacon: "Plato had signified the same sense, when he said, 'All the great arts require a subtle and speculative research into the law of nature, since loftiness of thought and perfect mastery over every subject seem to be derived from some such source as this. This Pericles had, in addition to a great natural genius. For, meeting with Anaxagoras, who was a person of this kind, he attached himself to him, and nourished himself with sublime speculations on the absolute intelligence; and imported thence into the oratorical art whatever could be useful to it.' " 1 Along with Emerson's division of English writers into Platonists and non-Platonists goes his emphasis .upon the Platonists outside of English Literature, whom he advises us to read as truly great men. The portion of his essay, Books, which he devotes to such authors bulks larger than any other single group of writers. He includes Plato, Plutarch, the later Platonists, Plotinus, Porphyry, Proclus, Synesius, lamblichus, the so-called Zoroas- trian Oracles and the remains of Hermes Trismegistus. The last two he classes among 1 Ibid., 241. 3H THE TEACHERS OF EMERSON the Bibles of the world. It is thus a collec tion of books which reflects his own reading and his appreciation of the worth of the Platonists in the world of literature. The writings of Plato and the Platonists, then, were the feeding ground for Emerson's mind. Just as the landscape artist keeps in constant touch with the play of light and shade, with the form, the color and the minutest detail that awakens his sense of beauty that his canvas may give back the freshness of the scene he surveys; so Emer son, by repeated and reverent readings in the old philosophers, toned his mind in unison with their speculation that his work might have something of its calm, grand air of in tellectual sovereignty. These books were to him a piece of nature and fate. And he at tended only to the utterances that had a mes sage for him. It is as if a lone, wandering astral body had swept through the old systems of thought, wrested away a fragment here, a fragment there, and so violently drawn them to itself that their impact fired the central mass with burning energy. What the at tractive power of Emerson's mind is, is dis cernible when these fragments of thought are examined. It is a mind that is tyrannized ASCENDENCY OF PLATONISM 315 over by a unifying instinct, that delights in a sense of ceaseless movement or flux, that has an affinity for beauty, that finds its highest endeavor realized either in a consciousness of the moral value of the world or in a mystical union with the moral reality itself, and that insists above all else on its own independence. BIBLIOGRAPHY BACON, FRANCIS. The Works of Francis Bacon. Ed. by Basil Montagu. 16 vols. London, 1825-1836. BOSANQUET, BERNARD. A History of ^Esthetic. Lon don, 1892. BUTCHER, S. H. Aristotle's Theory of Poetry and Fine Art. Second edition. London, 1898. CABOT, JAMES ELLIOT. A Memoir of Ralph Waldo Emerson. 2 vols. Boston and New York, 1895. COLERIDGE, SAMUEL TAYLOR. The Complete Works of Samuel Taylor Coleridge. Ed. by Professor Shedd. 7 vols. New York, 1868. Correspondence of Thomas Carlyle and Ralph Waldo Emerson, The. 2 vols. Library edition. Ed. by Charles Eliot Norton. Boston and New York, 1894. COUSIN, VICTOR. Introduction to the History of Phi losophy, translated from the French by Henning Gotfried Linberg. Boston, 1832. CUDWORTH, RALPH. The True Intellectual System of the Universe, to which are added the Notes and Dis sertations of Dr. J. L. Mosheim, translated by John Harrison, M.A. 3 vols. London, 1845. DE GERANDO, M. Histoire Comparee des Systemes de Philosophic. 4 vols. Paris, 1822. 317 318 BIBLIOGRAPHY EMERSON, RALPH WALDO. The Complete Works of Ralph Waldo Emerson. Centenary edition. Ed. by Edward Waldo Emerson. 12 vols. Boston and New York, 1903. FIELDS, A. Mr. Emerson in the Lecture Room. In the Atlantic Monthly, June, 1883. HARRIS, W. T. Emerson's Orientalism, in Genius and Character of Emerson. Ed. by F. B. Sanborn. Bos ton, 1885. IAMBLICHUS, On the Mysteries of the Egyptians, Chal deans, and Assyrians, translated from the Greek by Thomas Taylor. Second edition. London, 1895. Life of Pythagoras, or Pythagoric Life, translated from the Greek by Thomas Taylor. London, 1818. L'ESTRANGE, ROGER. Seneca s Morals by way of Ab stract. London, 1746. OCELLUS LUCANUS. On the Nature of the Universe, translated from the original by Thomas Taylor. London, 1831. PAULSEN, FRIEDRICH. Immanuel Kant: 'His Life and Doctrine, translated from the revised German edition by J. E. Creighton and Albert Lefevre. New York, 1902. PLATO. The Works of Plato, translated from the Greek by Thomas Taylor. 5 vols. London, 1804. BIBLIOGRAPHY 319 The Works of Plato, translated from the Greek by H. F. Gary, H. Davis, G. Burges. Bonn's Classical Library. 6 vols. London, 1848-1850. The Dialogues of Plato , translated into English by B. Jowett. 4 vols. New York, 1873. PLOTINUS. An Essay on the Beautiful, translated from the Greek by Thomas Taylor. London, 1792. ^^five Books, translated from the Greek by Thomas Taylor. London, 1794. On Suicide, translated from the Greek by Thomas Taylor. London, 1834. Select Works, translated from the Greek by Thomas Taylor. London, 1817. Contains extracts from the treatise of Synesius On Providence, with an introduc tion containing the substance of Porphyry's Life of Plotinus. PLUTARCH. Plutarch's Essays and Miscellanies. Com prising all his works collected under the title of Morals, translated from the Greek by several hands. Corrected and revised by William W. Goodwin, Ph.D., with an introduction by Ralph Waldo Emer son. 5 vols. Boston, 1906. Plutarch's Lives, translated from the original Greek by John and William Langhorne. First Worcester edition. 6 vols. Worcester, 1804. PROCLUS. The Six Books of Proclus on the Theology of Plato, translated from the Greek by Thomas Taylor. 2 vols. London, 1816. Contains a trans lation of Proclus' Elements of Theology, of his trea tises, On Providence and Fate, Ten Doubts con- 320 BIBLIOGRAPHY cerning Providence, and On the Subsistence of Evil. The Commentaries of Proclus on the Timteus of Plato, translated from the Greek by Thomas Taylor. 2 vols. London, 1820. TAYLOR, THOMAS. A Collection of Chaldean Oracles. In the Classical Journal, 1817, 1818. INDEX American Scholar, The, 222. Antagonism, see under Pyth- agoreanism. Anti-nomianism, 302. Art, 189. Art, 186, 187-188, 195. B Bacchus, 274-275. Bacchus, 275. Bacon, Francis, Emerson on, 23-24, 49, 311-312; First Philosophy of, 49-51, 311- 312; identified with Plato, 312-313; quoted, 49-51. Beauty, 172. Beauty, theory of, 172-184. Being, no, 120. Blight, 74-75. Books, 28. Brahma, 278. By-laws of the mind, 46-48. Categorical imperative, 299- 300. Categories of reason, 21. Celestial Love, 158. Character, 236. Christianity, doctrines of, 279-287. Circles, 128. Circle, symbolism of, 239. Coleridge, S. T., correlation of matter and mind in, 42- 45 ; Emerson on, 289-290 ; Emerson's debt to, 22-23, 297-298; on aim of the Friend, 22; on Bacon and Plato, 22 ; on intuition, 296- 297; on Kant, 296-297. Comic, 178. Compensation, 109-110, 113- 114. Correlation of matter and mind, 40-46. Cousin, Victor, 20-21 ; 265. Cupid, 256. Cupido, 256-257. Cudworth, on art, 189, 190; on daemons, 153; on the gods, 201-202; on nature, 34; on Pan, 252-254; on Pantheism, 64-65; on plas tic nature, 188-189; on Proteus, 255-256; on trans migration, 276; on Univer sal Mind, 80-81. 32I 322 INDEX Daemons, 148-153 ; 258-261. Damonic Love, 150-153. De Gerando, 70, 73. Each and All, 175-177, 179. Ecstasy, 29, 116, 118-119, 212- 214, 291-292. Emanation, 62-64, 122, 291. Emerson, as a critic, 219; elements of Neo-Platonism in, 24; errors in quoting, 226-227; his interpretation of Plato, 8, 10, II ; his in dices, 26, 33, 230, 238, 288; his debt to Coleridge, 22- 23, 297-298; his identifica tion of Bacon and Plato, 312-313; his Neo-Plato nism, 12; his Pythagorean- ism, 17, 18, 20; his relation to Transcendentalism, 290- 293, 305-306; on Bacon, 23-24, 49, 311-312; on books, 25; on Coleridge, 289-290; on Cudworth, 15; on English Platonists, 311; on early philosophers, 13, 33; on German philosophy, 289; on Goethe, 310; on Montaigne, 309-310; on Oracles, 6; on Orientalism, 265; on Plato, 13, 29, 263, 279; on Plutarch, 15-16; on Shakespeare, 308; on Swedenborg, 306-308 ; on Synesius, 5; on Taylor, 7- 8; his reading, in Cousin, 20; in De Gerando, 16, 20; in Plato, 20, 29-30; in Platonists, 5-7, 117; effects of, 27-29; marner of, 25, 26; in German philosophy, 287-288. Eternity, 38-39, 137, 240, 269- 270. Ethics, sovereignty of, 52. £tienne de la Boece, 161-163. Evil, 281. Fall of man, 248, 284. Fate, 133. Flux, 56-68. Friendship, 158. Friendship, 158-164, Furies, the, 258. Goethe, 310. Good of evil, 237. H Hegel, 289. Hypostases, 83. I lamblichus, on mystic union, 93; on daemons, 148; on friendship, 159-160; on symbols, 203; on fall of man, 248; on prayer, 282- 283; on imbecility, 286. INDEX 323 Ideas, 53, 59. Illusions, 267. Illusion, 266-272. Imbecility, 285-286. Immortality, 134-137. Indifferency, 108-115. Initial, D&monic and Celestial Love, 146-157. Intellect, 27. Intellect, 125-126, 130, 132- 134- Intuition, 294-295; 298. Jacobi, 302-304, Jove, myth of, 235-237, 242- 244. Kant, 288, 289, 292, 294, 296, 299, 300, 301, 305- Microcosm, 71, 72. Montaigne, 309-310. Music, 142. Mysticism, 92-105, 119, 162, 270. Myths, in Emerson, 222-245; in Plato, 221; rationalized, 250-262. N Nature, 34, 40, 41, 76, 77, 124, 186, 247. Nature, antagonism in, 68- 69; conscious life of, 66- 67; an effect, 122-123; an effluxion, 249; method of, 55-68; mysticized, 116-124; restoration of, 73-76; sym bolism of, 35-48; unity of, 72-73; a work of ecstasy, 116-119. Law, 41, 42-45, 58-59, 267- 268. Lecture on the Times, 39. Line, symbolism of, 239. Love, 164. Love, 164-172 ; celestial, 153- 155; daemonic, 151-153. Lyncaeus, 206, 207. M Maia, 266. Matter, 112-113. Ocellus Lucanus, 117. Ode to Beauty, 174, 179. One, the, doctrine of, 83-84, 87, 89; self-sufficient, 106- 107. See 'Mysticism. One Man, myth of, 222-227. Oracles, on ecstasy, 212-214; on poetry, 207-208; on na ture, 132; mysticism in, 94; Emerson on, 6. Orientalism, 264-279. Orphic Poet, 246-248. Over-Soul, The, 88, 95, 299. Over-Soul, the, doctrine of, 324 INDEX 84-90, 162, 273; in art, 191- 192; name, 277. Pan, 255. Pan, myth of, 251-255. Pantheism, 64-66. Plato, 10. Plato, on creation, 37, 194; on early philosophers, 14; on evil, 237, 281-282; on flux, 56-58; on idea, 59; on immortality, 136-137; on love, 146, 163, 171 ; on names, 35, 205; on original men, 222-223 ; on poetic in spiration, 214, 276; on rem iniscence, 157, 272; on the Good, 53; on time, 38, 240; relations with East, 264; symbolism in, 36-38. Plotinus, as philosopher, 205; being in, no, 120; dialectic in, 129; mysticism in, 92- 97, 105, 162, 270; on arche types, 156; on the arts, 193; on beauty, 173; on celestial love, 155; on contemplation, 67, 275 ; on creative power of soul, 121 ; on divinity, 304; on emanation, 63, 122; on ecstasy, 211; on immor tality, 135 ; on intellect, 126, 156; on intuition, 297; on matter, 112; on the One, 127, 156; on punishment, 241 ; on submission, 123 ; on Universal Soul, 139. Plutarch, on beauty, 181, 184; on daemons, 148, 150; on the Furies, 257; on human lot, 242; on love, 165-170; on sun, 249; on symbolism, 35-36; on brothers, 223. Poet, a liberating god, 210; as ideal man, 218; as scientist, 206 ; different from philosopher, 208; his inspiration, 210, 214; his re lation to man of action, 200; his use of symbols, 202, 203. Poetry, and science, 205 ; defi nition of, 207; Proclus' ac count of, 195-200. Polarity, 69. Prayer, 282-284. Proclus, on Bacchus, 275; on beauty, 177, 179, 183; on the daemon, 149; on defects, 257 ; on evil, 281 ; on fall of man, 284; on fate, 131, 132; on good of evil, 238; on immortality, 138; on line and circle, 239; on microcosm, 72; on mythol ogy, 251 ; on poetry, 195- 200; Pythagoreanism in, 19. Proteus, 255-256. Pythagoreanism, 17, 18, 19, 69, 70, 108, 115, 159-160, 216, 245. R Reason, 295. Regeneration, 75. INDEX 325 Reminiscence, 272-274. Representative Men, 16. Rhymes, 215-217. Schelling, 289. Self -Reliance, 108. Self-reliance, 106-108, 283, 291. Seneca, 226. Shakespeare, c^- Simplicius, 128. Sin, 280. Smaragdine Table, 217. Solitude, 06-97, 158-161. Soul, 75-76, 78-80, 88, 120- 121. See Over- Soul. Sphinx, The, 228-235. Sphinx, 227-235. Swedenborg, 306. Synesius, 152, 230. Symbolism, of line and circle, 239; of nature, 35-40; in poetry, 202-204. Taylor, Thomas, 4, 7, 8, 9, 19, 142, 143, 230, 231. Thinking, 126, 128. Time, 38, 39, 240, 269, 270. Transcendentalism, 287-306. Transcendentalist, The, 291, 302. Transmigration of souls, 272- 277. Trinity of beauty, truth and goodness, 182, 201, 292; Platonic, 79. Two-Rivers, 61-62. U Understanding, 295. Unity of things, 72-75, 268- 269. Universal Mind, 80-82, 186^ 191, 225, 300-301. Uriel, 237-241. Vice, III-II2. W World-Soul, The, 141-142. World-Soul, The, 139-144. X Xenophanes, 73. Z Zoroaster, see Oracles. HOME USE CIRCULATION DEPARTMENT MAIN LIBRARY This book is due on the last date stamped below 1-month loans may be renewed by calling 642-3405 6-month loans may be recharged by bringing books' to Circulation Desk. Renewals and recharges may be made 4 days prior to due date. ALL BOOKS ARE SUBJECT TO fiECALL 7 DAYS AFTER DATE CHECKED OUT. ' 1 3 1975 9 6 REC. en. FEB 1 8 1979 2 9 7988 OCT 0 9 1993 L- '89 LD21 — A-40m-5'74 (R8191L) General Library University of California la Berkeley U.C. BERKELEY LIBRARIES CDDbSSSSOl 208545.